• No results found

John Stuart Mill and freedom of expression

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2020

Share "John Stuart Mill and freedom of expression"

Copied!
307
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

JOHN STUART MILL

AND FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION

A thesis submitted to the University of London

in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of

Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D.)

by

Kevin Charles O’Rourke

Bentham Project, Department of History

University College London

(2)

ProQuest Number: U641898

All rights reserved

INFORMATION TO ALL USERS

The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed,

a note will indicate the deletion.

uest.

ProQuest U641898

Published by ProQuest LLC(2015). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved.

This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC.

ProQuest LLC

789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346

(3)

ABSTRACT

This thesis challenges traditional interpretations of John Stuart M ill’s theory of freedom

of expression, as exemplified in On Liberty (1859), by way of an examination of his

other publications and correspondence. The first section outlines the evidence for the

influences exerted on him during his youth, and examines his writings prior to 1859. His

father’s writings on the liberty of the press provide a framework within which to

interpret M ill’s earliest work on the same topic. Charges that Mill subsequently

abandoned support for this perspective are examined and dismissed, while the

importance of the influence of Samuel Taylor Coleridge is highlighted. The role of

M ill’s wife in the formation and articulation of his mature ideas on individuality and

liberty is emphasised.

On Liberty itself is the subject of the second section. Mill’s knowledge of criticisms by

reviewers is used as a base from which to examine his defence of freedom of thought

and discussion. The priority of the right to hear over the right to express opinions is

clarified, and the essential anti-paternalism of Mill’s defence is identified. The

importance afforded to James Fitzjames Stephen’s refutation of Mill is questioned, and

historical and conceptual inaccuracies in some of the more prominent contemporary

interpretations are pointed out. A refutation of the idea that M ill’s defence of freedom of

thought and discussion does not rely on his principle of liberty is attempted, and a

reinterpretation of that principle is offered. Exceptions to freedom of expression are

investigated in this light.

The final section looks at Mill’s writings after On Liberty, outlining how in his role as

(4)

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Acknowledgements... 6

Introduction... 7

Section I Chapter 1 A worthy successor... 19

1.1 James Mill and the liberty o f the press... 20

1.2 John Stuart M ill’s early writings ... 30

1.3 The Westminster Review...38

1.4 Conclusion... 45

Chapter 2 The aftermath of the ‘mental crisis’...46

2.1 The gradual change... 48

2.2 ‘The Spirit o f the A ge’... 52

2.3 Growing individualism^... 64

2.4 Conclusion^...77

Chapter 3 Coleridgian agendas...78

3.1 Coleridge on liberty...79

3.2 Mill as Coleridgian... 86

3.3 ‘Bentham’ and ‘Coleridge’... 92

3.4 Conclusion... 107

Chapter 4 Joint productions?... 109

4.1 Harriet on toleration... 110

4.2 Joint progress... 114

4.3 Education and liberty^... 121

4.4 Towards On Liberty... 131

(5)

Section II

Chapter 5 On Liberty: the 1859 response... 136

5.1 Setting the scene... 137

5.2 The right to hear: understanding infallibility^... 142

5.3 The necessity o f intellectual challenge ... 155

5.4 Truths and half-truths... 165

5.5 Conclusion...171

Chapter 6 James Fitzjames Stephen and Liberty, Equality, Fraternity 173 6.1 Self-regarding acts and infallibility... 175

6.2 Liberty versus control... 182

6.3 Conclusion... 185

6.4 Appendix: three ‘new ’ letters from Mill to Stephen... 187

Chapter 7 On Liberty: recent interpretations... 196

7.1 One principle or two?...197

7.2 Gray’s defence o f M ill... 204

7.3 Mill and interest...209

7.4 Progress through intellect... 218

7.5 Conclusion...227

Chapter 8 Exceptions to freedom of thought and discussion...230

8.1 The com-dealer example... 231

8.2 Forms o f incitement...236

8.3 Indecency and censorship... 248

(6)

Section III

Chapter 9 After On Liberty: from theory to reality...260

9.1 Liberty in practice... 261

9.2 The Inaugural Address...267

9.3 Mill in parliament... 270

9.4 After Westminster... 279

9.5Conclusion... 283

Chapter 10 Conclusion... 285

(7)

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

The origin of this thesis lies in ideas which first occurred to me during 1988-89 while I

was completing a minor dissertation for an M.A. degree in philosophy at University

College Dublin. Under the supervision of John Baker in the Department of Politics

there, I first began to take John Stuart Mill seriously as a thinker and to believe that his

defence of freedom of thought and discussion offered more than I had previously been

led to perceive. My introduction to Professor Fred Rosen at the Bentham Project in the

Department of History at University College London came about through Ted

Honderich, who helped me with my original proposal for this thesis. Professor Rosen

has proved to be an inspirational critic at all times, whose patient attention to my work

has brought a reasoned balance to my writing and ideas. Largely due to his enthusiasm I

have managed to produce this thesis in just over four years, while registered as a part-

time student: my sincere thanks, Fred. Above all however, my gratitude is due to

Deirdre, my wife, whose encouragement, support and patience over the past ten years

have inspired me to believe in my ability to complete this project: inadequate as it may

be, the thesis is dedicated to you. Dee.

(8)

INTRODUCTION

This thesis examines critically the development of John Stuart Mill’s writings on

freedom of thought and expression. Although his theory is best known from the

argument in the second chapter of On Liberty, which has become a source for practically

every subsequent discussion of freedom of speech, the thesis represents the first attempt

to understand the evolution of M ill’s ideas concerning freedom of thought and

discussion throughout his life, drawing not only from On Liberty but from his many

other writings on the subject.^ It is argued that, under the influence of various figures.

Mill moved from the Radicals’ notion of freedom of the press as a security against

corruption in government, to a deeper appreciation of the necessity of intellectual

freedom for individuals in order to promote their own happiness and thereby contribute

to the good of society. The thesis also challenges the view that Mill cannot be regarded

as consistent throughout his career in his support for freedom of expression.^

In addition to considering the evolution of Mill’s thought, the thesis offers an

interpretation of On Liberty itself which challenges many of the traditional and

contemporary readings of the essay. For almost a century On Liberty was regarded as a

self-contained philosophical tract, and was read in isolation from M ill’s other writings.

Recent philosophers such as John Rees, John Gray and John Skorupski have done much

to correct the imbalance of such interpretations, examining the ideas of On Liberty in

^ On Liberty, in The Collected Works o f John Stuart Mill, vol. XVTU, ed. John M. Robson (London and Toronto, 1963-91), pp. 213-310. All subsequent references to the

Collected Works will here be designated by CW, followed by volume and page numbers. Alan Haworth has recently referred to M ill’s argument as ‘the classic version of the classic defence’ - see Alan Haworth, Free Speech (London, 1998), p. 3.

(9)

the context of other writings, especially the System o f Logic and Utilitarianism? Yet,

largely as a result of the efforts of such thinkers, it has become commonplace to regard

M ill’s defence of freedom of thought and discussion as incompatible with the rest of the

essay: most commentators now agree that the second chapter of On Liberty is based on a

principle other than M ill’s principle of liberty/ This thesis argues that M ill’s defence of

freedom of thought and discussion in On Liberty is consistent with the principle of

liberty, and attempts to introduce a clearer understanding of that principle, consistent

with the manner in which Mill himself defended it.

For convenience. Mill’s writings have been divided into three chronological periods,

which are discussed in the three sections of the work. The first section covers M ill’s

many influences and writings on the freedom of the press which preceded the

appearance of On Liberty. The second section looks at On Liberty itself and the many

direct responses to that work, from nineteenth-century reviews to current commentary.

The third and final section examines M ill’s writings on intellectual freedom during the

remaining years of his life, following the appearance of On Liberty. In discussing this

material, the practical application of M ill’s ideas regarding freedom of expression is

emphasised.^

Freedom of the press was an extremely topical issue in early nineteenth-century Britain,

not least in the circles into which Mill was bom. While successive governments

^ John C. Rees, John Stuart M ill’s On Liberty, ed. G.L. Williams (Oxford, 1985); John Gray, Mill On Liberty: A Defence, 2nd edn (London, 1996); John Skompski, John Stuart Mill (London, 1991). A System o f Logic (CW VU, VIII); Utilitarianism (CWX).

^ See Rees, op. cit., p. 98; Skorupski, op. cit., p. 376; Himmelfarb, op. cit., p. 24; Ted Honderich, Punishment: The Supposed Justifications (London, 1989), p. 194; Roger Crisp, Mill on Utilitarianism (London, 1997), p. 190.

(10)

regarded restrictions on the press as essential to the preservation of law and order, the

Radicals advocated liberalisation as essential to progress and democracy.*^ In Chapter 1,

the intellectual legacy of James Mill, Jeremy Bentham and others is examined. In the

elder M ill’s Common Place Book, ‘Foremost of all the topics is the subject of the

Liberty of the Press’.^ His best-known defence of press freedom appeared in the

Encyclopaedia Britannica, written as a companion piece to his famous essay on

government.^ Less well appreciated is the fact that James Mill had also defended the

freedom of the press on more than one occasion in articles which appeared in the

Edinburgh Review, possibly as early as 1807. John Stuart Mill was unquestionably

familiar with and influenced by such writings.^

While still quite young, Mill was made familiar with the implications of freedom of

thought for religious and political belief. His earliest press writings reflect this

awareness, not least his 1825 Westminster Review article on the liberty of the press.

Although he later chose not to republish this article, it undoubtedly can be regarded as a

milestone in his intellectual development as it represents a first attempt to discover ‘to

what extent restraints upon the freedom of the press can be considered as warranted by

sound principles of political philosophy’.” Although John Stuart Mill believed that he

did not find his own voice until after his ‘mental crisis’ of 1826-27, that voice never

entirely abandoned the ideas of James Mill.

^ See W.H. Wickwar, The Struggle fo r the Freedom o f the Press, 1819-1832 (London, 1928).

^ Alexander Bain, James Mill: A Biography (London, 1882; repr. New York, 1967), p. 464.

^ See James Mill, Political Writings, ed. Terence Ball (Cambridge, 1992). ^ S&t Autobiography, CWI, p. 95.

Ibid. p. 11, where the Reformation is described as ‘the great and decisive contest against priestly tyranny for liberty of thought’.

(11)

Chapter 2 challenges the notion (expounded by Gertrude Himmelfarb, John Robson and

others) that Mill abandoned his support for freedom of the press during his reaction

against his u p b rin g in g A fte r his mental crisis, under the influence of Romanticism

and Idealism, Mill began to appreciate the value of viewpoints from outside the Radical

entourage of Bentham. Influenced by the scientific, positivist approach which he

discovered in the writings of Auguste Comte, he applied new ideas concerning progress

and history, to contemporary events in the run-up to the Reform Act of 1832.^^ These

influences are evident in his 1831 series of essays for the Examiner entitled ‘The Spirit

of the Age’.^'^ There, the importance of leadership is stressed and the value of discussion

in an era of upheaval and uncertainty is emphasised. However, this thesis argues that to

read such ideas in the manner of Himmelfarb, who argues that they undermine freedom

of thought and discussion as defended in On Liberty, is incorrect. M ill’s mature ideas

regarding individuality and intellectual freedom had not developed at this stage: he still

regarded freedom of the press as a political rather than a social necessity. Yet, in his

own words, he was in ‘an intermediate state - a state of reaction from logical-utilitarian

narrowness of the very narrowest kind, out of which after much unhappiness and inward

struggling I had emerged, and had taken temporary refuge in its extreme opposite’. B u t

nowhere is it consistently evident that he lost his commitment to the idea of freedom of

the press. Himmelfarb’s conclusions, it is argued, are often based on selective and

incomplete readings of the texts. Similarly, the evidence from Mill’s published writings

See note 2 above.

Unused pages of the early draft of \h& Autobiography, CWI, Appendix G, p. 615. CW XXn, pp. 227ff.

(12)

and private correspondence alike contradicts the idea that at this time Mill developed a

life-long, covert commitment to elitism/^

In 1834, Mill confided in a private letter that ‘Few persons have exercised more influence

over my thoughts and character than Coleridge has’.^^ Chapter 3 investigates this often

under-appreciated influence of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, especially in relation to the

idea of individuality and the importance of intellectual freedom/^ Coleridge’s

commitment to freedom of the press differed from that of Bentham and James Mill,

focusing as it did on the importance of the individual rather than on the necessity of

political dissent: in fact, Coleridge supported the traditional dictum of English law,

much ridiculed by the Radicals, that a libel is all the worse for being true.^^ Emphasising

the importance of the individual mind in the discovery of truth, Coleridge also stressed

the importance of not mistaking half-truths for the whole, of keeping truth alive in the

individual mind, and the necessity of guarding against the dangers of intellectual

stagnation, all ideas which later found their way into On Liberty?^ An examination of

Mill’s assessments of Bentham and Coleridge in his famous essays on these two

‘seminal minds’ demonstrates the importance which Mill began to attach in the 1830s to

An idea put forward by, among others, Joseph Hamburger. See his Intellectuals in Politics: John Stuart Mill and the Philosophic Radicals (New Haven, Connecticut and London, 1965); How Liberal was John Stuart Mill? (Austin, Texas, 1991); ‘Individuality and Moral Reform: The Rhetoric of Liberalism and the Reality of Restraint in M ill’s On Liberty", Political Science Reviewer, vol. 24, 1995.

C W X a, pp. 220-23.

Autobiography, CW I, p. 161; see Christopher Turk, Coleridge and Mill: A Study o f Influence (Aldershot, 1988).

The Friend, in The Collected Works o f Samuel Taylor Coleridge, ed. Barbara E. Rooke (Princeton, 1969-), vol. 4, part I, pp. 93-94.

(13)

intellectual freedom for the sake of the individual/^ Much of this change, it is argued, can

be traced to the influence of Coleridge and his followers.

However, to Mill, the person who wielded the most profound influence over him was

undoubtedly Harriet Taylor, who became his wife in 1851.^^ As far as Mill was

concerned, she was co-author of works subsequent to the System o f Logic, and On

Liberty was especially representative of her thinking.^^ Yet the extent of her intellectual

influence remains a moot point among Mill scholars.^"^ She had committed her thoughts

on toleration and individuality to paper in an untitled essay, probably dating from the

early 1830s.^^ As Mill felt that his views had fully matured by the year 1840, his

growing commitment to individuality during the 1830s must be seen as complementing

Harriet’s ideas, if not actually deriving substance from them.^^ His writings throughout

the 1840s and in the 1850s demonstrate a growing fear of the power of public opinion

and conformity, and a belief in the importance of individuality. The belief that

intellectual progress must precede all other forms of social progress became fully

articulated at this time. Moreover, a firm commitment to freedom of the press and

intellectual freedom in society became prominent, and at one point Mill even indicates a

willingness to condone violent revolution where such freedom is denied.^^

‘Bentham’, London and Westminster Review, August 1838; ‘Coleridge’, ibid. March 1840, CWX, pp. 75-115 and 116-63.

^^Autobiography, CWI, pp. 192ff.

23

Ibid. pp. 258, 259.

See the (unattributed) introduction to CWI, p. xvii.

^ The undated manuscript is in the British Library of Political and Economic Science at the London School of Economics, Mill-Taylor Collection, Box m . No. 78. The paper is watermarked 1832.

^^Autobiography, CWI, p. 229.

(14)

Section two deals with On Liberty. From the very beginning, it was recognised as an

important work, and its defence of freedom of thought and discussion was hailed as a

worthy successor to Milton’s Areopagitica. Yet, it also provoked controversy, not least

because of its pronouncements on Christianity in the context of that defence. Discussing

the work in his private correspondence, rarely referred to by interpreters of On Liberty,

Mill said that he had deliberately wanted to kindle such controversy, and explicitly

mentioned the reviews which had appeared in the Dublin University Magazine and The

English Churchman?^ Chapter 5 uses these reviews as a basis from which to examine

On Liberty itself, as many of the arguments voiced in these early pieces continue to be

used by critics today. At the outset the priority which On Liberty's arguments place on

the right to hear all opinions over the right to express all opinions is identified, a priority

previously unrecognised and certainly important. The claim that all silencing of

discussion is an assumption of infallibility is explained in this manner by Mill himself,

and the second chapter of On Liberty is shown to take its cue from this starting point.

The right to hear is grounded in the notion of individuality, which is consequently

shown to lie at the heart of Mill’s arguments for freedom of thought and discussion.

That Mill was anxious to rebut charges of elitism which could be brought against the

doctrine of On Liberty is shown by reference to his correspondence where he denies

outright that his intention lay in this direction.^^

The criticisms levelled by James Fitzjames Stephen in Liberty, Equality, Fraternity have

influenced almost all subsequent discussions of On Liberty?^ Yet, when examined

closely in Chapter 6 of this thesis, Stephen’s interpretation is shown to do Mill less than

justice. While appreciating the fact that freedom of thought and discussion is at the heart

(15)

of the principle of liberty, Stephen proceeds to misconstrue M ill’s defence. His basic

argument is that government can interfere in the life of the individual for the sake of the

larger good of society, and his overall perspective is at odds with Mill’s fundamental

standpoint. He attempts to show that discussion cannot play the role in society which

Mill attributes to it and that liberty can be pernicious to the majority of people. His

elitist utilitarianism serves as a contrast to Mill’s position, and demonstrates the integral

part played by intellectual freedom in the principle of liberty. (This chapter, in addition,

carries an appendix in which three previously unknown letters from Mill to Stephen,

discovered in the course of my research, are outlined and analysed.)

Chapter 7 looks at more recent and contemporary commentary on On Liberty. Here, the

idea that Mill’s defence of freedom of thought and discussion is not based on the

principle of liberty - an idea popular among recent interpreters - is examined, and an

attempt is made to demonstrate that such an idea is unnecessary to a proper

interpretation of the ideas of Chapter 2 of On Liberty. The importance attached to the

notion of ‘interests’ in these current interpretations is examined.^^ Moreover, the

influential interpretations of John Gray and John Skorupski of the notion of interests are

questioned, as is the validity of Gray’s recent criticism of M ill’s ideas concerning

p ro g re s s .A new approach to reading On Liberty is then posited, based on the evidence

of the actual text and M ill’s other writings. Heretofore, the principle of liberty has been

interpreted in terms of harm to others: I suggest that the emphasis should instead be

placed primarily on the idea of harm to self. Such a reading views the principle of

liberty as anti-patemalist at its core, rather than regarding anti-patemalism as an

James Fitzjames Stephen, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (London, 1873).

See, for example, John Rees, ‘A Re-reading of Mill on Liberty’, Political Studies, vol. 8, 1960.

(16)

implication or by-product of that principle. This reading of the principle of liberty is

shown to fit with M ill’s defence of freedom of thought and discussion in a manner

which is more than merely coincidental. Mill’s other published writings as well as his

private correspondence support such an interpretation. On Liberty, based on utilitarian

concerns, holds that liberty should have priority wherever it is acknowledged that all

people are fundamentally distinct as individuals. When individuals achieve their own

happiness, the maximum happiness can thereby be achieved. It is argued that this

position is similar to that held by Mill in his later essay. Utilitarianism?^

The connection between the expression of opinion and the performance of actions

harmful to others forms the starting point of Chapter 8, which examines the exceptions

to freedom of thought and discussion admitted by On Liberty. The famous com-dealer

passage and Mill’s example of incitement to tyrannicide are examined in the light of the

revised interpretation presented, and are shown to be consistent with that

interpretation.^"^ The distinction between speech acts and other actions is brought into

focus. That On Liberty sets down no precise criteria by which the difference between

harmful incitement and innocent debate can be established is noted, and the

interpretations of H.J. McCloskey, D.H. Monro, Gray and others are examined.^^ Mill’s

attitude to racist speech is assessed, the importance of individuality to his overall

scheme is again emphasised, and the role of truth in his arguments is again examined.

In private correspondence. Mill explained utilitarianism as the sum total of individual happiness - see his letter to Henry Jones, 13 June 1868, CWXVI, p. 1414.

On Liberty, CW XVIII, pp. 260, 228n.

H.J. McCloskey, ‘Liberty of Expression - Its Grounds and Limits (I)’, Inquiry, vol. 13, 1970; D.H. Monro, ‘Liberty of Expression: Its Grounds and Limits (II)’, Inquiry,

(17)

The issue of indecency, usually discussed by commentators in the context of M ill’s

exceptions to freedom of thought and discussion, is also addressed in this chapter.^^

The third section of the thesis examines M ill’s writings after On Liberty. The

publication of the essay in 1859 brought with it a popular notoriety which Mill had not

previously enjoyed. His fame extended far beyond Britain, and his subsequent election

as Member of Parliament for Westminster added to the impact of his ideas on his

contemporaries. During this period of public life, he was regularly called upon to

express his views and to explain his positions on various topics, not least on the issue of

freedom of speech. A study of these writings, as well as other more formal writings,

provides the basis for Chapter 9. Together they serve to demonstrate that Mill regarded

his theories as practical in their application to society rather than mere intellectual

deliberations which had little or no bearing on real life.^^ The importance of active and

informed intellects to progress and improvement (and through the intellectual to the

moral nature of the individual) is one of the central issues of On Liberty which

continues into M ill’s other works, such as his Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform

(which also first appeared in 1859), Considerations on Representative Government and

Utilitarianism (both 1861), dîtià Auguste Comte and Positivism (1865). M ill’s defence of

utilitarianism is shown to be consistent with the interpretation of On Liberty expounded

in this thesis.

The issue of intellectual freedom, especially as regards morality and religion, is again

broached through Mill’s Inaugural Address as Rector of St Andrew’s University,

(18)

delivered in February 1867.^^ Yet again, the central role played by the intellect in

developing one’s individuality is emphasised by Mill. His many speeches to the House

of Commons and to public meetings similarly emphasised the importance of freedom of

thought and discussion to the well-being of the individual and the progress of society.

Moreover, his appreciation of the benefits of freedom of speech when employed as

demonstration rather than merely as discussion was evident in his reactions to events

such as the Hyde Park riots of 1866 and their aftermath.^^ Thus he emphasised the

absolute value of freedom of speech in a democratic society, while he also demonstrated

the practical application of his ideas regarding in c ite m e n t.T o the end of his life. Mill

continued to maintain that liberty held the key to human happiness, and that intellectual

freedom was the first and most important part of such liberty.

In the concluding chapter, I again attempt to sum up and demonstrate the overall

consistency in the development of Mill’s work. It is argued that Mill’s theory is richer

than interpreters and critics generally allow. It is again emphasised that it is not abstract

truth for its own sake that Mill defends but, rather, the discovery of truth for the sake of

individuality. This thesis ultimately contends that On Liberty can be fully understood

only in the context of M ill’s other writings. Attempts to treat as a rigorous philosophical

tract what Mill himself described as ‘a kind of philosophic text-book of a single truth’

are therefore bound to fail, not least because interpreters often mistake what that single

truth actually is."^^ Freedom of thought and discussion play a primary role in encouraging

In addition to Haworth, op. cit., this charge is made by, among others, Francis Canavan in his ‘J.S. Mill on Freedom of Expression’, M odem Age, vol. 23, Fall 1979, p. 369.

CIV XXI, pp. 215-57. CWXXVin.p. 103.

See, for example, his attitude to the Fenian movement, as expressed in a letter to G.W. Sharpe, 1 June 1867, CIFXVI, p. 1275.

(19)

diversity and individuality, regarded by Mill as essential if society is to progress and

achieve the greatest possible happiness for the individuals who are its members. In this

manner Mill believed himself to be continuing but developing the tradition of utilitarian

(20)

SECTION I

CHAPTER 1

A WORTHY SUCCESSOR

In January 1807, when John Stuart Mill was less than one year old, the Edinburgh

Review published an article which held that ‘The liberty of the press is, indeed, the most

inestimable security of... a people, because it gives that tone to the public feelings, on

which all liberty must ultimately rest’.^ Such words could have been used to describe the

position subsequently defended by Mill throughout his life. After his death in 1873, c

wrote of him in the Fortnightly Review that: ‘The value of [his] wise and virtuous

mixture of boldness with tolerance, of courageous speech with courageous reserve, has

been enormous’; and that this disposition, in conjunction with the famous second

chapter of On Liberty in support of freedom of expression, ‘has been the chief source of

that liberty of expressing unpopular opinions in this country without social persecution,

which is now so nearly complete, that he himself was at last astonished by it’.^

Unquestionably, Mill’s influence on the issue of freedom of expression in nineteenth-

century Britain (and further afield) was enormous. Yet, in the course of his life, the

platform from which he addressed the question changed: initially emphasising the

political importance of the freedom of the press for good government, he later stressed

the social importance of freedom of thought and discussion for individual development.

Moreover, he held that both viewpoints could be defended within a utilitarian

framework. The route which he followed from the issues of his youth to the issues of his

^ ‘The Science of Legislation, from the Italian of Gaetano Filangieri’, Edinburgh Review, vol. 9, January 1807, p. 365.

(21)

later life involved contact with a wide variety of thinkers. To trace that route and to

examine the influence of those thinkers on his approach to freedom of expression is the

goal of the present work.

1.1 James M ill and the liberty o f the press

The author of the 1807 Edinburgh Review article on press freedom cited above

bemoaned the fact that ‘the liberty of the press does not exist, nor ever did exist in

England, but by connivance’.^ In 1811 James Mill, also writing in the Edinburgh,

quoted the earlier article with approval to demonstrate that ‘the opinions which we now

deliver have not been hastily adopted, and are not the immediate suggestion of any

particular occurrence to which the public attention may have been recently attracted

The elder Mill questioned the wisdom of the undefined nature of the law of libel as it

then existed in Britain, and defended the notion that ‘If men would only employ a little

patient consideration in forming their notions, we should not despair of getting all but a

few, to join with us in opinion, that, so far from the freedom of the press being the cause

of the French revolution, had a free press existed in France, the French revolution never

^ ‘The Science of Legislation, from the Italian of Gaetano Filangieri’, lac. cit.

^ ‘Mémoires de Candide sur la liberté de la presse’, Edinburgh Review, vol. 18, May 1811, p. 101. Press prosecutions had achieved particular notoriety in 1809 through a libel case involving the Duke of York. (Jeremy Bentham’s The Elements o f the Art o f Packing, as Applied to Special Juries: Particularly in Cases o f Libel Law was produced at this time as an attack on the system whereby juries in such libel cases were selected by ministers and judges, who could thereby ensure the outcome of the trial. Somewhat ironically, that work was itself not publicly circulated until 1821.) The Wellesley Index to Victorian Periodicals on CD-ROM, ed. W.B. Houghton (London, 1999) identifies James Mill as the author of the 1811 article using evidence from the Brougham Manuscript Lists in the Ogden Papers, University College London Library. It does not identify the author of the 1807 article, but suggests ‘Henry Hallam’ as a possible candidate. However, the cited passage suggests that James Mill may have been the author of the earlier article: Henry Brougham’s Autobiography claims that Mill began contributing to the Edinburgh in 1807 - see Alexander Bain, James Mill: A Biography

(22)

would have taken p la c e '/ This radical position on the question of press freedom and

libel law became a regular and favourite idea of James M ill/

That the importance of freedom of thought was impressed by James Mill on his eldest

son in this early period is related by John Stuart Mill in the posthumously published

Autobiography? It should come as no surprise, therefore, that this topic constitutes the

subject of some of John Stuart M ill’s earliest published writings, along with tracts

against religious persecution and the law of libel as it was enforced in England in the

opening decades of the nineteenth century. We can be in no doubt that he perceived a

connection between the practice of religion and the right to freedom of expression: in

the Autobiography he explicitly defines the Reformation as ‘the great and decisive

contest against priestly tyranny for liberty of thought’.*

The topic of freedom of expression remained close to the heart of James Mill

throughout his eldest son’s formative years: subsequent to the 1811 article, he appears to

^ ‘Mémoires de Candide sur la liberté de la presse’, p. 121.

^ See Bain, op. cit., pp. 98ff.; Joseph Hamburger, James Mill and the Art o f Revolution

(New Haven, Connecticut and London, 1963), pp. 27ff. In addition to James M ill’s published writings on the issue of freedom of the press, his Common Place Book (four volumes, presented by John Stuart Mill to the London Library in January 1872) shows extensive research into all aspects of the topic, including newspaper cuttings and personal notes. Bain, in his biography of James Mill, comments on the contents of that book: ‘Foremost of all the topics is the subject of the Liberty of the Press. On this he had accumulated opinions and illustrations from the wide compass of ancient and modem literature. The general drift is, of course, in favour of Liberty, with practical refutations of the various subterfuges for evading the application of the principle’ (Bain, op. cit..

Appendix B, p. 464).

^ Autobiography, CWI, p. 45.

(23)

have taken on the subject in the Edinburgh Review yet again in 1815/ and in 1821 he

proposed that he himself should undertake the entry on liberty of the press for Macvey

Napier’s fifth edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica}^ The piece, in addition to his

articles on government and jurisprudence, was soon acknowledged as a classic defence

of the radical cause and was reprinted subsequently as a pamphlet. Jeremy Bentham’s

interest in libel and press freedom also continued after The Elements o f the Art o f

Packing: he wrote a series of letters to the Spanish people on this very topic in October

1820, urging them to resist any imposition made upon the liberty of their press by laws

being drafted at that time, on the grounds that ‘whatsoever evil can result from this

liberty, is everywhere, and at all times, greatly outweighed by the good’.^^ For Bentham

and James Mill alike, the freedom to discuss ideas in public and to criticise government

and its institutions was an essential element in the struggle against corruption among the

ruling classes, a topic at the heart of the agenda of the group of radical thinkers which

centred around Bentham. Their ideas reflected the growing discontent with traditional

models of government and society.

In the aftermath of the French Revolution, the young Mill was stimulated by the debates

concerning reform of the British constitution. Throughout the country, the possibility of

a similar revolution was widely feared: ‘Many persons felt that society was resting on

^ ‘Liberty of the Continental Press’, Edinburgh Review, vol. 25, June 1815, pp. 112-34. The Wellesley Index identifies Mill as author of this article on the basis of letters from Francis Place and David Ricardo.

A letter to Napier, dated 3 January 1821, says: ‘1 believe 1 have now fulfilled all the obligations, in the way of articles, which 1 am under to you. There is one article more, however, which, if you have not otherwise provided for it, 1 shall be very glad to undertake. That is. Liberty of the Press, or Libel Law, whichever title you choose to range it under. 1 think on that subject 1 could throw a good deal of light’ - cited in Bain,

op. cit., p. 193, who also records a letter from James Mill dated 21 August 1821 informing Napier that he was not pleased with the finished article. See Hamburger, op. cit., p. 27, n. 18.

(24)

crumbling foundations, and this made every expression of discontent... appear

ominous’.O p in io n s which supported the need for reform were viewed with suspicion

by those in power, while any opinion which attempted to undermine Christianity -

regarded as being at the very heart of law and order - was met with alarm. Yet, long-

held ideas concerning religion, government and the status quo were being questioned

openly. That the lower classes - now becoming more literate and consequently

susceptible to influences from a far broader spectrum of ideas than their forefathers -

should begin to question religious principles, or have a right to question their own status

or the status of their ‘betters’, was considered especially dangerous. In 1821, one

newspaper observed that:

The libels of former times were only read by the higher classes, which possessed

the means of detecting their falsehood - those of the present times are exclusively

read by the lower orders, who are destitute of all means of arriving at the truth....

Former libels attacked only measures of policy and men - present ones attack laws

and institutions. Former libels were only intended to drive a ministry from office -

the object of the present ones is to dethrone the King and overthrow the

Constitution. Moreover, to render their effects still more destructive, the poison of

a great number of them is spewed forth on the Sabbath.^^

In the years of John Stuart M ill’s youth, a person could be found guilty of libel by

instilling dissatisfaction with the government or the constitution: freedom of the press

was freedom within the confines of the law, and was certainly not unrestricted. In 1811

James M ill’s article in the Edinburgh Review had cited a legal case where it had been

(25)

pointed out that ‘if a publication be calculated to alienate the affections of the pec^le, by

bringing the government into disesteem, whether the expression be ridicule or obloquy,

the person so conducting himself is exposed to the inflictions of the law: - It is a

c r i m e 'T h e elder Mill commented: ‘Now, to point out any fault in the government

undoubtedly tends to bring, so far, the government into disesteem. Therefore, to point

out any fault in government, is a liberty not allowed to the press by the law of

England’.

The term ‘libel’ at this time was used in relation to any expression of opinion in the

press, including the publication of facts: truthful utterances could be libellous if they

were considered disagreeable by a judge, thought liable to disturb the peace or otherwise

to cause widespread dissatisfaction. Truth or falsity were irrelevant: in fact, ‘the greater

the truth, the greater the libel’ was a common idiom of the time.^^ From the very

beginning of his career as a writer and thinker, at the time of what he later called his

‘youthful propagandism’, John Stuart Mill clearly placed himself on the side of those

who held and professed opinions which sought to overthrow the old political order and

to replace it with an order based on reason and consensus, where rational debate won the

New Times, 5 January 1821, quoted in W.H. Wickwar, The Struggle fo r the Freedom o f the Press, 1819-1832 (London, 1928), p. 183.

‘Mémoires de Candide sur la liberté de la press’, p. 100. Mill was citing Lord Bllenborough in The King versus Gobbet, 24 May 1804.

Ibid. pp. 100-1. Note also that James Mill, in a letter dated 10 September 1819, was quick to reassure the publisher of the Encyclopaedia that ‘You need be under no alarm about my article Government. I shall say nothing capable of alarming even a Whig, and he is more terrified at the principles of good government than the worst of Tories’ (cited in Bain, op. cit., p. 188).

(26)

day and intellect triumphed over the blind acceptance of tradition/^ Looking back on

that period fifty years later, Mill commented:

Freedom of discussion even in politics, much more in religion, was at that time far

from being, even in theory, the conceded point which it at least seems to be now;

and the holders of obnoxious opinions had to be always ready to argue and reargue

for the liberty of expressing them/^

Mill specifically mentioned Richard Carlisle, whose position at the forefront of the

movement to establish a free press at the time was notorious, and who doggedly defied

all attempts to silence him. In 1817, Carlisle began deliberately to provoke the

government by publishing works considered immoral. Imprisoned initially for

publishing political parodies which mocked the Church of England, upon his release he

used Sherwin ’s Weekly Political Register to serialise the works of Thomas Paine. (Paine

had been tried and prosecuted for publishing his unorthodox ideas concerning religion

and politics almost thirty years previously.) Encouraged by the lack of government

response, Carlisle next reprinted Paine’s political writings in two volumes.

Subsequently in 1818 he published Paine’s Age o f Reason, a work which challenged

Christianity and the nature of revealed r e lig io n .T h e radical press was, in turn,

encouraged by the success of men such as Carlisle and started to become more

outspoken.^^ Growing discontent with the prevailing political situation also manifested

Autobiography, Chapter 4 is named ‘Youthful Propagandism. The Westminster Review’ {CWl, pp. 88ff.).

Ibid. p. 89.

This work had previously been condemned as blasphemous, its publishers convicted in 1797 and 1812. The American edition of this work (1794) carried a message from Paine to his readers: ‘He who denies to another this right, makes a slave of himself to his present opinion, because he precludes himself the right of changing it’ - cf. On Liberty, CWXVIII, pp. 229ff.

(27)

itself in meetings and public gatherings convened to address the problems discussed in

the press. In August 1819, such a meeting was called at St Peter’s Fields in Manchester

to consider the most appropriate means of pressing reform on parliament. As Henry

Hunt (a radical for whom a warrant had been issued) was about to address the meeting,

armed constabulary attempted to arrest him. The crowd was charged, resulting in the

death of eleven people and the injury of over four hundred. Carlisle had been in

attendance and subsequently published an eyewitness account of the ‘Peterloo’

massacre. Outrage at the actions of the yeomanry was echoed in newspapers and

journals up and down the country, and calls to arms became the demand of the day.^^

The official response to the widespread unrest came in December with the passing of the

‘Six Acts’, two of which related directly to the freedom of the press. One allowed for

the confiscation of all copies of a published work deemed libellous and, in the event of a

second offence, banishment of the author. Another attempted to enforce a strict code of

practice on newspapers by introducing criteria regulating subject matter, frequency of

publication, and size and amount of paper used, imposing a minimum price of 6d

(excluding the 4d stamp duty). To sell unstamped publications was to be an offence

punishable by fine. Moreover, printers and publishers of newspapers covered by the new

laws were obliged to pay a pre-determined security in advance of publication against

any possible libel fines which they might subsequently incur. These measures were

explicitly intended to crush the growing circulation of radical newspapers and, in

(p. X X X , n. 15) estimates that a circulation of 3,000-5,000 was typical in the 1820s; see

also Wickwar, op. cit., pp. 29-30. However, readership was high, and public houses and reading rooms were the gathering points for people to read or to hear read aloud publications which actively criticised the government, the Church and the Crown.

(28)

consequence, to reduce demands for reform. As Lord Ellenborough explained to the

House, having stressed that the Bill was being introduced because of the ‘pauper press’:

‘The mischief arising from them in the deception and delusion practised upon the lowest

classes by means of the grossest and most malignant falsehoods, was such that it

threatened the most material injury to the best interests of the country, unless some

means were devised of stemming its torrent’. A g a i n s t the background of an

overbearing regime which regarded the silencing of controversy as necessary to the

well-being of society, James Mill’s Encyclopaedia Britannica article on the liberty of

the press was a radical and brave stance. This article, although composed subsequent to

- but not independently of - his articles on government and jurisprudence, provided the

theoretical basis for most of John Stuart’s thought and early writings on the subject of

freedom of expression.^^

The piece begins with the admission that ‘The offences capable of being committed by

the press are indeed nearly co-extensive with the whole field of delinquency’; it

proceeds to investigate the role of the press, briefly in relation to individuals and, for the

main, in relation to government; and it closes with an examination of the possible

limitations which can be imposed on freedom of discussion in general.^"^ James Mill

assumes that when a published libel upon a private individual is proved in court, that

individual should receive appropriate reparation. If the general public continues to

believe the libel after such a ruling, it must be because people are aware of additional

facts which were not available to the judge, or else because the general public is unable

Parliamentary Debates, House of Lords, 29 December 1819.

In the first paragraph of James M ill’s ‘Liberty of the Press’, reference is made to the articles ‘Government’ and ‘Jurisprudence’. All three are included in James Mill,

Political Writings, ed. Terence Ball (Cambridge, 1992) - page references are to this edition.

(29)

to form correct opinions based on factual evidence. If the latter is the case, then ‘it is the

fault of the legislature; and for the rectification of this evil, the best course undoubtedly

is, to take effectual measures for the instruction of the people, which instruction would

soon place them beyond the danger of such delusions’.H o w e v e r , such a course of

action would not prove attractive to a government wishing to keep society in a servile

state of mind and which therefore maintained an interest in keeping education and truth

from the majority. It would not be until the interests of the rulers and the interests of its

citizens were at one that good government could be achieved. This was the central thesis

of the article ‘Government’ and one of the main themes famously attacked by Thomas

Babington Macaulay in the Edinburgh Review?^ Among the many criticisms raised by

Macaulay was the vague and indeterminate nature of such ‘interests’ - a criticism

echoed in recent interpretation of On Liberty^ where the notion of interests has again

become prominent.^^

For James Mill, the liberty of the press provides a means whereby resistance to

corruption in government becomes possible. Such a possibility must always be left open

or the people are inevitably left in misery and degradation. In matters of government

‘The real point of importance is, to establish correct opinions in the minds of the

Ibid. p. 103. The stamp duties imposed on publications were popularly known as ‘taxes on knowledge’. The phrase ‘knowledge is power’ was popularised by Richard Carlisle - on 28 April 1822, for example, he wrote in The Republican: ‘Let us then endeavour to progress in knowledge, since knowledge is demonstratively proved to be power’.

‘M ill’s Essay on Government: Utilitarian Logic and Politics’, Edinburgh Review, vol. 49, March 1829, pp. 159-89; repr. in Ball, op. cit. For the debate which ensued, see George L. Nesbitt, Benthamite Reviewing: The First Twelve Years o f the Westminster Review, 1824-1836 (New York, 1934), pp. 139-44. For John Stuart Mill’s own assessment of the debate, see his Autobiography, CWI, pp. 165-66.

(30)

people’. T h u s the distinction between factual evidence and subjective opinion is subtly

introduced, a distinction which has a precedent in Plato’s Republic}^ Freedom of

discussion - where all opinions are presented equally and no advantage or obstruction is

placed in the way of any single opinion - he lauded as the sole method whereby most

people can arrive at true opinions based on the evidence presented to them.^° Liberty of

the press plays a central role in this process:

Every subject has the best chance of becoming thoroughly understood, when, by

the delivery of all opinions, it is presented in all points of view; when all the

evidence upon both sides is brought forward, and all those who are most interested

in showing the weakness of what is weak in it, and the strength of what is strong,

are, by the freedom of the press, permitted... to devote to it the keenest application

of their faculties. False opinions will then be delivered. True; but when are we

most secure against the influence of false opinions? Most assuredly when the

grounds of these opinions are the most thoroughly searched.^^

If a government makes itself responsible for choosing what the public should hear, that

government is acting in a despotic manner. Against the notion that the press must be

restricted in order to stop the spread of unrest, James Mill argues that calls to arms by

the press, if they result in open rebellion, are not the first but the final stage of resistance

- there must be some pre-existing consensus towards the taking up of arms, or any

exhortation will mean nothing: ‘we think it may be satisfactorily shown, that no

James Mill, ‘Liberty of the Press’, in Ball, op. cit., p. 123.

Plato’s Republic (v. 477-78) distinguishes between knowledge and belief. John Stuart Mill had read and made an abstract of the Republic as early as 1819, and later held that, like James Mill before him, there was no author to whom he owed a greater debt for

‘mental culture’ {Autobiography, CW l, p. 25).

(31)

operation of the press, however directly exhorting to this species of resistance, ought to

be treated as an offence’.H o w e v e r, regarding incitement, he subsequently explains in

a passage remarkably similar to the famous ‘com-dealer’ example used at the start of

Chapter 3 of On Liberty that: ‘A hand-bill, for example, distributed at a critical moment,

and operating upon an inflamed state of mind, in a narrow district, may excite a mob to

disturb the proceedings of a court of justice, to obstruct police officers in the execution

of their duties, or even to disturb, on this or that occasion, the deliberations of the

legislature itself However, there is always a problem with distinguishing between

passionate and dispassionate language, because ‘A word which may excite strains of

emotion in one breast, will excite none in another’

7.2 John Stuart MiWs early writings

James M ill’s Encyclopaedia article on the liberty of the press concludes with an

assertion that people ought especially to have the power to choose their own opinions on

religious matters.^^ And it is precisely on the point of liberty of discussion and religious

freedom that the sixteen-year-old John Stuart Mill made his debut in the Morning

Chronicle on 1 January 1823. Described in M ill’s own bibliography as a letter ‘on Free

Discussion, signed. An Enemy to Religious Persecution’, it challenges the notion that

" Ibid. p. 127. Ibid. p. 112.

Ibid. p. 113 - cf. On Liberty, CW XVIH, p. 260. James Mill comments that acts such as these ‘are clearly hurtful acts; they may be very accurately defined; and penalties, of moderate severity, would be sufficient to deter from the performance of them’.

James Mill, in Ball, op. cit., p. 134.

(32)

‘Christianity is part and parcel of the law of England’. T h i s widely endorsed notion -

which purportedly demonstrated that any opinions which undermined Christianity were,

in fact, a veiled attack on the civil law - was traditionally used in debates and law courts

against religious dissenters. Indeed, such were the prevailing attitudes that ‘Those who

were not of the Anglican faith could not be regarded as completely English’. M i l l ’s

letter attempts to show that these arguments are not worthy of serious consideration. He

proceeds in a quasi-legal manner not unlike that employed by his father.^^ It cannot be

Christian morality which is meant when people use such phrases, he maintains, or all of

the Christian precepts would have to be a part of the law. Such a scheme would be

impossible to enforce. Neither can it be the doctrines and truths of Christianity which

are meant - what Mill, following his father, is careful to label the opinions of the

religion - because precepts and opinions are logically distinct. The law protects

Christianity by persecuting those who express contrary opinions, but it cannot offer a

basis as to why it should do this, other than to maintain rather lamely that such

persecution is part of the law. This reasoning, the young Mill concludes, is totally

absurd.

The tone of the letter is precocious and the content is very much in keeping with the

opinions of James Mill. Yet, the piece anticipates John Stuart Mill the logician. Its

importance, however, lies not so much in the techniques used but in the evidence it

provides of the young Mill taking a public stance for intellectual and religious freedom

at such an early stage in his publishing career. Moreover, the idea of ‘opinion’ holding

c w x x n , pp. 6-8.

Bernard Wishy (ed.). Prefaces to Liberty: Selected Writings o f John Stuart Mill

(Boston, 1959), ‘Introduction’, p. 35.

(33)

the central part in debate on most issues was to be very important for Mill, playing an

essential role of his defence of freedom of expression throughout his life. The upshot of

the letter’s argument is that because debates concerning religion are dealing not with

matters of empirical fact but with matters of speculative opinion, the truth cannot be

ascertained in the same manner as in mathematics or logic, a position which John Stuart

Mill held throughout his life.

This first published piece was a brave (although probably supervised) stand for the

cause of intellectual and religious freedom, using a line of argument that was considered

blasphemous at this time. The connection between Christianity and the law had similarly

been questioned as part of the defence used by Susannah Wright, one of Richard

Carlisle’s supporters. Carlisle’s role in the spread of dissent in the wake of Peterloo had

prompted the Lord Mayor to issue a warrant for his arrest on charges of seditious libel.

Already facing other charges of blasphemous libel for the publication of Paine’s works,

a conviction was soon secured, and Carlisle remained in prison for six years. His work

was continued on the outside by his wife and sister, who in turn were arrested and

imprisoned. Their fight was taken up by Susannah Wright who, having been arrested on

charges brought against her by the self-styled Society for the Suppression of Vice, in her

defence had questioned the connection between Christianity and the law. However, it

was Carlisle himself who had written the defence used in court, subsequently publishing

the supposedly blasphemous arguments in the Republican, which he continued to edit

from behind bars.^^

(34)

These events are explicitly mentioned in the Autobiography in connection with a series

of letters written by John Stuart Mill which were published in the Morning Chronicle in

January and February 1823. ‘The prosecutions of Richard Carlisle and his wife and

sister for publications hostile to Christianity,’ he tells us, ‘were then exciting much

attention, and nowhere more than among the people I frequented.... I wrote a series of

five letters under the signature of Wickliffe going over the whole question of free

publication of all opinions on r e l i g i o n T h e s e letters draw extensively on the writings

of both James Mill and Bentham, and mention the Encyclopaedia Brittanica article on

the liberty of the press as a ‘most satisfactory’ exposition of the topic. Yet the arguments

are very narrow in focus, and while they can be said to achieve their purpose, it is

questionable whether they really come to grips with the issue of freedom of speech at

all. The first letter challenges those who believe that free discussion contributes to the

discovery of truth on most subjects to show why it should not equally contribute to the

truth on religious matters. If people are not allowed to choose their own opinions, then

the government must be choosing their opinions for them: ‘But if the Government is

allowed to chuse opinions for the people, the government is d e s p o t i c T h i s line of

argument, borrowed almost verbatim from James Mill, was to be resurrected by John

Stuart Mill again and again in various forms: because opinion with regard to religion

does not deal with matters of fact but with subjective feelings regarding what is true,

people should be allowed to make up their own minds by weighing the evidence on all

sides. To decide for others which opinions are worthy of their consideration is to have

ultimate power over them. It may be generally felt that atheism is false, but this is not a

valid reason for preventing discussion on the topic ‘since before discussion, if their

CW I, p. 89. The letters {CW XXII, pp. 9ff.) were, in fact, signed ‘W ickliff (without the final ‘e ’) after the fourteenth-century religious reformer.

(35)

opinions are true it is only by accident, whereas after it they hold them with a complete

conviction, and perfect knowledge of the proofs on which they are grounded'/^ There is

an appreciation in this letter of the dignity of possessing knowledge and of the necessity

of individual choice, both notions to which Mill maintained a lifelong commitment and

which appear to be derived directly from James Mill. This commitment in turn was

fuelled by a belief in progress and individual development which was to be used as the

intellectual driving force behind On Liberty.

In the second letter of the series. Mill examines the notion that to allow the spread of

‘infidel doctrines’ leads to private morality being undermined, thereby leading to the

demise of what was widely held to be the only security of ‘good judicature’.^ The letter

proceeds to show that although Christianity may appear to be at the heart of maintaining

law and order, public opinion regarding what is acceptable is more fundamental than

Christianity and is that which primarily influences people’s actions. In the courts, for

example, swearing on a Christian Bible ostensibly guarantees truth in the judicial

system, but this guarantee can be demonstrated as a sham: jurists at a trial, for example,

swear to judge on the evidence given but will sometimes find criminals guilty of lesser

offences than the evidence warrants if a statutory punishment is thought excessive for a

Morning Chronicle, 28 January 1823, CW XXU, too. cit.: cf. James Mill, in Ball, op. cit., p. 129: ‘...it is not safe for the people to let any body choose opinions for them. If it be said, that the people themselves might be the authors of this preference, what is this but to say, that the people can choose better before discussion than after; before they have obtained information than after it? No, if the people choose before discussion, before information, they cannot choose for themselves. They must follow blindly the impulse of certain individuals, who, therefore, choose for them’.

On Liberty'^ phrase ‘man as a progressive being’ is also found in James M ill’s writings on education: see Geraint Williams, ‘The Greek Origins of J.S. Mill’s Happiness’, Utilitas, vol. 8, 1996, pp. 8ff.

(36)

particular instance of the c r i m e S i m i l ^ l y public opinion accepts ‘duelling and

fornication’ although both are forbidden by Christianity. The letter concludes that the

argument regarding the necessity of Christianity to the preservation of society is

essentially without foundation in practice.

The third letter of the series aims ‘to prove that persecution [of infidels] is not necessary

for the preservation of Christianity’."^^ To persecute non-believers, Mill contends, is to

assume ‘the utter incapacity and incorrigible imbecility of the people’ insofar as it

assumes that the Christian populace is so easily swayed that it is unable to distinguish

truth from falsehood."^^ Yet, through their Christian upbringing and education, the

people are already favourably predisposed towards opinions which support Christianity,

and consequently the persecution of infidels cannot be justified on the grounds that these

opinions will mislead Christians. Moreover, as it is generally believed that people prefer

the comfort of faith to the insecurity of doubt, persecution seems unjustified unless it is

also believed that the Christian public at large is in danger of embracing non-belief. If

anything, opposition to blasphemies serves mainly to advertise and give life to opinions

which would otherwise die out of their own accord."^^ Such opposition usually amounts

to little more than abuse which is ‘far easier and requires less time and application than

argument’. In England, Christians would fare far better. Mill implies, by trying to offer

His other examples include import-export merchants who regularly falsely swear regarding the quality and amount of their goods, and entrants to Oxford University who swear to obey the outdated statutes of the university. The argument here draws on Bentham’s writings on oaths - see the introduction to the letter at CWXXU, p. 12.

Morning Chronicle, 12 February 1823, ibid. p. 15. Ibid. p. 16.

References

Related documents

The suggestions of this research are explained as follows: UIN Alauddin Makassar needs to increase the factor of female leadership style and organizational culture

environmental policies, and the responsibility to ensure that activities within their jurisdiction or control do not cause damage to the environment of other States or of areas

Should you have detailed questions pertaining to the information contained in this document, you may contact Michco, or the manufac- turer which provided the original information

There also remains a lack of consensus regarding the volume of fugitive CH4 emissions lost from leak-prone distribution infrastructure, the frequency of leaks per road mile, and

Agreement under the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC). One cannot provide a clear answer to this question unless there is an understanding of the

Whereas carbon capture and storage (CCS) coupled to coal or gas power production offers the potential to decarbonise the current centralised power systems, this relies on a

Whereas carbon capture and storage (CCS) coupled to coal or gas power production offers the potential to decarbonise the current centralised power systems, this relies on a

Examining the history of jazz in Korea will inform us of the ways that Western popular music was introduced and established, how Korean people incorporated such music into