• No results found

Secure Implementation in Queueing Problems

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2020

Share "Secure Implementation in Queueing Problems"

Copied!
5
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

Secure Implementation in Queueing Problems

Katsuhiko Nishizaki

Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University, Toyonaka, Japan Email: [email protected]

Received August 3, 2012; revised September 5, 2012; accepted October 7, 2012

ABSTRACT

This paper studies secure implementability (T. Saijo, T. Sjöström and T. Yamato, “Secure Implementation,” Theoreti-

cal Economics, Vol. 2, No. 3, 2007, pp. 203-229) in queueing problems. Our main result shows that the social choice

function satisfies strategy-proofness and strong non-bossiness (Z. Ritz, “Restricted Domains, Arrow-Social Welfare Functions and Noncorruptible and Non-Manipulable Social Choice Correspondences: The Case of Private

Alterna-tives,” Mathematical Social Science, Vol. 4, No. 2, 1983, pp. 155-179), both of which are necessary for secure imple-

mentation, if and only if it is constant on the domains that satisfy weak indifference introduced in this paper. Weak in- difference is weaker than minimal richness (Y. Fujinaka and T. Wakayama, “Secure Implementation in Economies with

Indivisible Objects and Money,” Economics Letters, Vol. 100, No. 1, 2008, pp. 91-95). Our main result illustrates that

secure implementation is too difficult in queueing problems since many reasonable domains satisfy weak indifference, for example, convex domains.

Keywords: Secure Implementation; Dominant Strategy Implementation; Nash Implementation; Strategy-Proofness;

Queueing Problems

1. Introduction

In this paper, we consider queueing problems of allo-

cating positions in a queue to agents, each of whom has a constant unit waiting cost, with monetary transfers. Ex- amples of such problems are the use of large-scaled ex-

perimental installations, event sites, and so forth1.

Strategy-proofness is a standard property for non-

manipulability: The truthful revelation is a weakly domi-nant strategy for each agent. However, the strategy- proof mechanism might have a Nash equilibrium which induces a non-optimal outcome. This problem is solved by secure implementation (Saijo, et al. [2]), that is,

dou-ble implementation in dominant strategy equilibria and

Nash equilibria2. Previous studies illustrate how difficult

it is to find desirable and securely implementable social

choice functions: Voting environments (Saijo, et al. [2];

Berga and Moreno [4]), public good economies (Saijo,

et al. [2]; Nishizaki [5]), pure exchange economies (Mi-

zukami and Wakayama [6]; Nishizaki [7]), the prob-lems of providing a divisible and private good with

monetary transfers (Saijo, et al. [2]; Kumar [8]), the

problems of allocating indivisible and private goods with monetary transfers (Fujinaka and Wakayama [9]), Shapley-Scarf housing markets (Fujinaka and

Waka-yama [10]), and allotment economies with single-peak- ed preferences (Bochet and Sakai [11]).

This paper is most closely related to the one written by Fujinaka and Wakayama [9]. They show a constancy result on secure implementation when the domain satis- fies minimal richness (Fujinaka and Wakayama [9]). Our model is a special case of their one and have many rea- sonable domains which do not satisfy minimal richness. On the basis of this fact, we study the possibility of se- cure implementation in queueing problems. Unfortunate- ly, our main result shows that only constant social choice functions satisfy strategy-proofness and strong non-bos- siness (Ritz [12]), both of which are necessary for secure

implementation, on the domains satisfy weak

indiffer-ence, which is weaker than minimal richness, introduced

in this paper.

This paper is organized according to the following sections. In Section 2, we introduce our model, properties of social choice functions, and domain-richness condi- tions. We show our results in Section 3. Section 4 con- cludes this paper.

2. Notation and Definitions

Let I

1, , n



n2

be a set of agents. Let

 

n

i i I I

    be a queue, where, for each iI, i

is the position for agent in the queue i  and for

each i j, I with , i j

1For queueing problems, see Suijs [1] and so forth.

2This concept is considered to be a benchmark for constructing

mecha-nisms which work well in laboratories. See Cason, et al. [3] for ex-perimental results.

.

ij  For each iI , let

(2)

where is a monetary transfer for agent . Let

be a profile of monetary transfers and be a profile of consumption bundles,

called an allocation. Let

i t

i I

t I

i

 

n

i

tt 

 

,  n

 

n

,

Z t

i

is a queue and

n n k k I I      

 

t 0

 

  

be the set of feasible allocations.

For each I , let ci

x x> 0

be a

unit waiting cost for agent and Ci  be a set

of unit waiting costs for agent . For each i

i 

iI, let

i be the utility function for agent

such that for each and each

:

u I  C  i

i,ti

 IciCi,

i, ;i i

i 1

i i.

ut c     ct

Let i Ii be the domain and i be

a profile of unit waiting costs. For each

C

C

 

i

I cc C

I

i , let

i j i j

j i   be a profile of unit waiting

costs for agents other than agent . i

 

j

:

ccC

C

i

Let f C

cC

Z

 

c t,

be a social choice function. For each

, let be the allocation associated

with the social choice function

 

cZ

f at the profile of unit

waiting costs and be the con-

sumption bundle for agent in the allocation

.

c

   

c

 

 

c

i

,

i c ti  II

,

c t

Saijo et al. [2] show that strategy-proofness and strong

non-bossiness are necessary for secure implementation.

Definition 1 The social choice function f satisfies strategy-proofness if and only if for each c c, C and

each iI,

, 1 ,

, 1 ,

i i i i i i i

i i i i i i i

c c c t c c

c c c t c c

                  

Definition 2 The social choice function f satisfies strong non-bossiness if and only if for each c c, C

and each iI, if

, 1 ,

, 1 ,

i i i i i i i

i i i i i i i

c c c t c c

c c c t c c

             c c  

then

i, i

 

,t c ci, i

c ci, i

,t c c

i, i

Fujinaka and Wakayama [9] show a constancy result on secure implementation when the domain satisfies minimal richness.

Definition 3 The domain satisfies minimal rich-

ness if and only if for each

C

iI, each c ci , i Ci, each

,

i i I

  

i

    

i i

, and each if , then there exists

,

T

 i i

i

TcciCi

such that

1)

 and



ciT

i i

  

 i i

2) ci

 i i

ci for each iI\

 i , i

.

The following example shows that many reasonable

Example 1 Let i I

domains do not

 and Ci. Moreover, let

3,ci 1, i 1, i 2 andT 2

i

c     . In this case, we

have

 i i 

ci 1T3

i  i

ci . Let ciCi

be such that

 i i

ciT , that is, ci 2. This

implies that con finition 3 h On the

other hand, if ci 2

dition 1) in De olds.

 , then

 i i

ci  2 3

ii

ci for  i 3 . This

h re im

k indif- fe

implies that condition 2) in Definition 3 does not old. Our main result implies a constancy result on secu plementation when the domain satisfies weak indif- ference which is weaker than minimal richness.

Definition 4 The domain C satisfies wea

rence if and only if for each iI, each ,c ci i Ci,

each  i , i I, and each T, if

ii 

ci  T

 i i

ci, then there exists ciCi

such that

 i i

ciT.

Remark 1 In our model, weak indifference is equi-

va

3. Results

lent to convexity3.

For simplicity of notation, let i i

c ci, i

,

,

i i c ci i

  , ii

ci,ci

,

c ci, i

  

i i

  ,

,

i i ci c

   

i and titi

c ci, i

, ti ti

c ci, i

,

,

i i i i

tt c c , titi

ci,ci

, tit ci

i,ci

for

each c c, C and each iI.

3.1. Preliminary Results

that the social choice func-

onetary transfer de

d each

In this subsection, we assume

tion f satisfies strategy-proofness.

Lemma 1 shows that each agent’s m

pends on her position in the queue given unit waiting costs for other agents. Since the proof is similar to Fuji-naka and Wakayama [9], it is omitted.

Lemma 1 For each ,c cC an iI , if

i i

 , then titi.

Lemma 2 shows that if su

there exists a unit waiting cost ch that some two different consumption bundles are indifferent in terms of utility level, then the position associated with the unit waiting cost is in between the two positions. In Lemma 2, we use the following notation:

for each iI, each ciCi, each

i,ti

 I , and

each i I, let ti

 i

i i

,ci

.

Lemma 2 Fo

i i ci t

   

and each i I

;  ,

ach c c,

i t

r e C  , if

i i

  and there exists ciCi such that

i 1

ci ti

i 1

ci ti

       , then iii.

here

ex

Proof. Suppose, by contradiction, that t ist

,

c cC and iI such that ii,

i 1

ci ti

i 1

ci ti

       for some ciCi, and

3For the relationship among weak indifference and certain

(3)

i i

 or ii. We consider the case of ii.

ypothe e have

By the h sis, w

. i i i i i t t c       

, we have

(1)

By the definition of ti

 ; ,t ,c

t

.

i i i i i

i i t  

 

 

the defi of and strategy-pr

c

(3) and

i ci

nition

t

uations

(2)

oofness, we

(3) By ha By Eq i t ve

; , ,

.4

i i i i i

ti   t

i i

 , we have cici.

Since we consider the case of ii, this implies

 ; ,t ,c

,t

,c

.

ti i i i i ti  i; i i i (

definition of

4)

, we have

and strategy-proofnes

By the ti s

 ; ,t ,c

 t

 ;

,t

,c

. This is a con-

we have a con-

tradiction to strategy-proofness in the case of i i

i i i i i i i

t t

4). Similarly,

i i i

Equatioi n (

tradiction to

. ■

3.2. Ma

“o

iI

in Result

e the “if”

i i

 

by cont

Theorem 1 Suppose that the domain satisfies

part is obvious, we only

C f

weak

prove the

r each

indifference. The social choice function satisfies stra- tegy-proofness and strong non-bossiness if and only if it is constant5.

Proof. Sinc

nly if” part. Let ,c cC. Firstly, we show

 

c c, ,t c c,

c c,

 

,t c c,

fo

xists j I

i iii ii

. Suppose, radiction, that there e 

, , s impli

such that c c strong

j, j

t c c

 

bossiness

 

, , ,

j j c cjj t c cj non- rategy-proofness, t

. By es

j

hi

  

and st

1 1 .

j cj tj j cj tj

  

       (5)

By Lemma 1, this implies j j or j j .

,

j j

 

 

, it also Si

n

nce

c c,

 

,t c c,

 ,t c c

,

by stro

implies

j j

 

g n and st roof

, j j c c rategy-p j j on-bossiness

ness

1 1 .

j cj tj j cj tj

       (6)

 

ns (5) an

Equatio d (6), we have

By

j j

j

j j

j

, this implies tha

j j

c t

ence

t   c

     . Si

t there exi

 

weak indiffer

nce C

sts

satisfies

j j

c C

such that

j 1

cj tj

j 1

cj tj.

       (7)

We consider the case of j  j. In th

Le

is case, by

mma 2, we have j jj . If  jj or

j j

 , then, by Equatio nd st on-

bossiness, we have

n (7) a rong n

j j

  . This is a contradiction.

Therefore, we know

.

j j j

 

By applying the above argument to the left inequality

repeatedly, we can find c cj, jCj such that j j

and

j 1

cj tj

j 1

cj tj

   

      , wher

exist

between

e there

s no position j and j induced by a

unit waiting cost for agent i given cj In this case, we

have or

.

j j j j

  . By

stron non-bossiness,

these imply jj. g

tradictio

This is a contradiction. Similarly,

we have a con n in the case of j j.

Without loss of generality, let i1. Ther ore, we ef

have

 

c c1, 1 ,t c c1, 1

c c1, 1

 

,t c c1, 1

. (8)

By the same argument stated above, we also have

 

c c c, , ,t c c c, ,

 

1 2 1,2 1 2 1,2

1, ,2 1,2 , 1, ,2 1,2 ,

c c c t c c c

 

 

   

(9)

where c1,2 is a profile of unit waiting costs for agents

an a

other th gents 1 and 2. By Equations (8) and (9), we

have

 

 

1 2 1,2 1 2 1,2

1 2 1,2 1 2 1,2

, , , , ,

, , , , ,

c c c t c c c

c c c t c c c

           .

By sequentially replacing by cj cj for each j1, 2

in this manner, we finally prove

   

c t c,

   

c ,t c

. ■

rem

Remark 2 The above theo does not depen

fin

d on the iteness of the number of positions, which is used to prove Claim 3 in Proposition 1 of Fujinaka and Waka- yama [9].

Obviously, constant social choice functions are se- curely implementable. Therefore, by bringing the above theorem together with a characterization of securely

implementable social choice functions by Saijo et al. [2],

we have the following constancy result on secure im- plementation.

Corollary 1 Suppose that the domain satisfies weak indifference. The social choice function is securely im- plementable if and only if it is constant.

Remark 3 In our model, Maskin monotonicity is not

st 6

4Note that the equality does not hold. If it holds, then we have

ronger than strategy-proofness . This relationship im- plies that our main result is established by secure im-

i i

cc by Equations (1) and (2). This implies that f should be a correspon-dence since we consider the case of  i i.

5For the tightness of this theorem, see Examples 2, 3, and 4 in

(4)

plementability but not by Nash implementability.

Remark 4 Saijo [14] shows the following constancy

re

ch uch that

sult on “Nash” implementation: The social choice function satisfies Maskin monotonicity and dual do- minance (Saijo [14]) if and only if it satisfies constancy. In line with such domination, Fujinaka and Wakayama [9] show the following constancy result on “secure” imple- mentation: The securely implementable social choice func- tion satisfies non-dominance (Fujinaka and Wakayama [9]) if and only if it satisfies constancy. Note that non-

dominance is weaker than dual dominance7. In our model,

similar to the relationship between minimal richness and weak indifference, we have a constancy result on secure implementation by a weaker condition than non-domi- nance as follows: for each

 ,t

 

,   ,t

f C

 

, ea

and

 

,

c c C s

 

   

c ,t c

 ,t

,



,

cC such tha

,

c  t

t

c t

 

no 

and each iI

i 

, if there exists

, , , ,

i i i i i

L  t c L  t c and

i,i , i

i,

L   t cL  ti ,ci , then there exists ciCi

such that

 i i

ci  ti ti , where

, , , 1

1

i i i i i i i i

i i i

Lt c t I c t

c t

 

 

   

 

   

for each iI, each ciCi and each

i,ti

 I .

4. Conclusion

secure implementability in queueing

5. Acknowledgements

.A. thesis presented to the

REFERENCES

[1] J. Suijs, “On and Budget

Bal-This paper studies

problems. Fujinaka and Wakayama [9] show a constancy result on secure implementation. Our model is a special case of their one and have many reasonable domains which do not satisfy minimal richness. However, we have the same constancy result under less restrictive domain-richness con-ditions. On the other hand, it remains to show domain-rich- ness conditions for the existence of non-constant securely implementable social choice functions. However, our main result implies that it is difficult to find such conditions that are reasonable in the economic sense.

This paper is based on my M

Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University. The author would like to thank an anonymous referee, Ta- tsuyoshi Saijo, Masaki Aoyagi, Yuji Fujinaka, Kazuhiko Hashimoto, Shuhei Morimoto, Shinji Ohseto, Shigehiro Serizawa, Takuma Wakayama, and seminar participants at the 2008 Japanese Economic Association Spring Meeting, Tohoku University, for their helpful comments.

The author is especially grateful to Tatsuyoshi Saijo, Yuji Fujinaka, and Takuma Wakayama for their valuable advices. The author acknowledges for the Global COE program of Osaka University for the financial supports. The responsibility for any errors that remain is entirely the author.

Incentive Compatibility

ancedness in Public Decision Making,” Economic Design, Vol. 2, No. 1, 1996, pp. 193-209.

doi:10.1007/BF02499133

[2] T. Saijo, T. Sjöström and T. Yamato, “Secure

Implementa-son, T. Saijo, T. Sjöström and T. Yamato, “Secure tion,” Theoretical Economics, Vol. 2, No. 3, 2007, pp. 203- 229.

[3] T. Ca

Implementation Experiments: Do Strategy-Proof Mecha-nisms Really Work?” Games and Economic Behavior, Vol. 57, No. 2, 2006, pp. 206-235.

doi:10.1016/j.geb.2005.12.007

[4] D. Berga and B. Moreno, “Strategic Requirements with Indifference: Single-Peaked versus Single-Plateaued Pre-ferences,” Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 32, No. 2, 2009, pp. 275-298. doi:10.1007/s00355-008-0323-y

[5] K. Nishizaki, “Secure Implementation in Discrete and

ness and

Imple-quivalence of Secure Implementability

.osaka-u.ac.jp/coe/dp/pdf/no.279_dp.pdf o- Excludable Public Good Economies,” Osaka Economic Papers, Vol. 61, No. 2, 2011, pp. 48-56.

[6] H. Mizukami and T. Wakayama, “Bossi

mentability in Pure Exchange Economies,” Vol. 1461, 2005, pp. 126-140.

[7] K. Nishizaki, “An E

and Full Implementability in Truthful Strategies in Pure Exchange Economies with Leontief Utility Functions,” GCOE Discussion Paper Series No. 279, Osaka University, Osaka, 2012.

http://www.iser

[8] R. Kumar, “Secure Implementation in Production Ec nomies,” Department of Economics Working Paper Series No. 2011-02, Louisiana State University, Louisiana, 2009. http://bus.lsu.edu/McMillin/Working_Papers/pap11_02.pdf [9] Y. Fujinaka and T. Wakayama, “Secure Implementation

in Economies with Indivisible Objects and Money,” Eco-nomics Letters, Vol. 100, No. 1, 2008, pp. 91-95.

doi:10.1016/j.econlet.2007.11.009

[10] Y. Fujinaka and T. Wakayama, “Secure Implementation in Shapley-Scarf Housing Markets,” Economic Theory, Vol. 48, No. 1, 2011, pp. 147-169.

doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0538-x

[11] O. Bochet and T. Sakai, “Secure Implementation in Al-lotment Economies,” Games and Economic Behavior, Vol. 68, No. 1, 2010, pp. 35-49.

doi:10.1016/j.geb.2009.04.023

[12] Z. Ritz, “Restricted Domains, Arrow-Social Welfare Func- tions and Noncorruptible and Non-Manipulable Social Choice Correspondences: The Case of Private Alterna-tives,” Mathematical Social Science, Vol. 4, No. 2, 1983, pp. 155-179.

6For the relationship among dual dominance, non-dominance, and

(5)

Secure Implementation in Queueing Prob-[13] K. Nishizaki, “

lems,” GCOE Discussion Paper Series No. 245, Osaka Uni-versity, Osaka, 2012.

http://www.iser.osaka-u.ac.jp/coe/dp/pdf/no.245_dp_revised.pdf

doi:10.1007/BF02499133 doi:10.1016/j.geb.2005.12.007 doi:10.1007/s00355-008-0323-y doi:10.1016/j.econlet.2007.11.009 doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0538-x doi:10.1016/j.geb.2009.04.023 doi:10.1016/0022-0531(87)90094-9

References

Related documents

In a recent study including nearly 1000 patients who were treated only in single hospital in South Korea, the reported risk factors for SPC in head and neck squamous-cell car-

Conrado Crucillo (son of the deceased Santiago Crucillo). Another agricultural land situated at Pulong Munti, is owned in common by the Heirs of Elena Crucillo,

Based on the household fixed effects approach, which is the one preferred in this paper, private sector workers who are legally entitled to severance pay earn roughly 12 percent

David Roberts joins the CCVS team as Registrar and Current Events Instructor.. David received his BA from Queen’s University and is busily preparing new students

As part of the comprehensive Risk Management Process our Risk Engineering service delivery focuses on the operational risks of your corporation or project respectively. Business Risks

To make DOIs accessible to the public, they must be registered with the EZID service. The ESDIS Project submits DOIs for EZID registration after ensuring that 1) the data provider

Keeping in mind the earlier calls for the moderating role of normative influences and based on the above discussion, this paper examines the moderating role of normative interpersonal

assign specific cellular functions to a distinct methylation event.. Chemical interference offers exquisite control over biological pathways since various concentrations of