Why Are Stabilizations Delayed?
(Article begins on next page)
The Harvard community has made this article openly
available.
Please share
how this access benefits you. Your story
matters.
Citation Alesina, Alberto, and Allan Drazen. 1991. Why are stabilizations delayed? American Economic Review 81(5): 1170-1188.
Published Version
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2006912
Accessed February 18, 2015 12:28:31 AM EST
Citable Link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:4553028
Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University's DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at
WHY ARE STABILIZATIONS DELAYED?
Alberta Alesina
Allan Drazen
Working Paper No. 3053
NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue
Cambridge, MA 02138 Auguat 1989
We wiah to thank Stephan Haggard, Elhahan Helpman, Peter Kenen, Barry Nalebuff, Jeff Sacha, and seminar participants in Princeton and Yale for very uaeful
comments. Aleaina'a research was aupported by the National Science Foundation, grant no. SES-8821441. Drazen's research was supported by the National Science Foundation, grant no. SES-87O6808. This paper is part of NBER's research program in Financial Markets and Monetary Economics. Any opinions expressed are those of the author not those of the National Bureau of Economic Research.
NBER Working Paper #3053
August 1989
WHY ARE STABILIZATIONS DELAYED?
ABSTRACTS
When a stabilization has significant distributional implications (as in the case of tax increases to eliminate a large budget deficit) different socio-economic groups will attempt to shift the burden of stabilization onto other groups. The process leading to a stabilization becomes a war of attrition', with each group finding it rational to attempt to wait the others out. Stabilization occurs only when one group concedes and is forced to bear a disproportionate share of the burden of fiscal adjustment.
We solve for the expected time of stabilization in a model of 'rational" delay based on a war of attrition and present comparative statics results relating the expected time of stabilization to several political and economic variables. We also motivate this approach and its results by comparison to historical episodes.
Alberto Ales
ma
Allan DrazenDepartment of Economics Department of Economics Harvard University Princeton University Cambridge, MA 02138 Princeton, NJ 08540
in the
long run. For instance, large deficits implyingpath of
government debt and accelerating inflation are allowed to continue even though it is
apparent
that
such deficits will haveto be
eliminated sooneror
later.A
puzzling question is why these countries do not stabilize immediately, onceit
becomes apparentthat
current policiesare
unsustainable
and
athat
change in policy will haveto be
adopted eventually. Delays in stabilization are particularly inefficientif
the longera
country waitsthe
more costly isthe
policyadjustment
neededto
stabilize, andif the
periodof instability
beforethe
policy change is characterized by economic inefficiencies, suchas
high and variable inflation.The
literature
onthe
pre—stabilization dynamics impliedby an
anticipated future stabilization (for example, Sargent and Wallace [1981], Drazenand
Helpman [1987,19891)assumes
that the
timing ofthe future
policy change is exogenous. Since in these models thelong—run infeasibility
of
current policy is known fromthe
beginning, what is missing isan
explanationof
whythe
infeasible policy is not abandoned immediately. Explanations ofthe
timing of stabilization based on
irrationality,
such as waitingto
stabilize until "things get reallybad",
are unconvincing: sincethe
deterioration inthe
fiscal position canbe
forseen, the argumentturns
on certain countries being more irrational than others. Explanations whichgive a key role
to
exogenous shocks leave unxeplainedboth
why countries do not stabilizeas
soonas
unfavorable shocks occur and why stabilizationsthat
are undertaken oftendon't
seemto
coincidewith
significant observable changesin
external circumstances.'In
Sargentand
Wallace (1981) and Drazen and Helpman (1987) the timingof
stabilization is deterministicand
exogenous; in Drazen and Helpman (1989) the timing is stochastic,but
the distributionof the time
of stabilization is exogenous.—2—
This paper argues
that the
timingof
stabilizations and, in particular,their
postponement cannot be understood in models
in
whichthe
policymaker is viewed as a socialplanner
maximizingthe
welfareof
a representative individual,On the
contrary, heterogeneityin the
population is crucial in explaining delays in stabilization Our basicidea
isthat
undercertain
circumstancesthe
process leading to a stabilization can be described as a "warof
attrition"
between different socio—economic groups with conflicting distributional objectives.This means, first,
that
delaysin
stabilizationarise
dueto a
political stalemate over distribution,and,
second,that
stabilization occurs when a political consolidation leadsto
a resolution of the distributional conflict.More specifically, when
it
is agreedthat
stabilization requires a changein
fiscal policy toeliminate
budget deficitsand
growing government debt,there
maybe
disagreement about howthe
burdenof the
policy change isto
be shared. When socio—economic groups perceivethe
possibility of shifting
this
burden elsewhere, each group mayattempt
to wait the others out. This war ofattrition
ends anda
stabilization is enacted when certain groups "concede" andallow
their
political opponentsto
decideon the
allocation of the burdenof
fiscal adjustment.Concession may occur
via
legislative agreement, electoral outcomes,or (as
is often observed)ceding power of decree to policymakers.
We present
a
simple modelof
delayed stabilization dueto a
war ofattrition
and derive the expectedtime of
stabilization as a functionof
characteristics ofthe
economy, including parameters meantto
capture, in a very rough way, the degreeof
political polarization. For example,the
more uneven isthe
expected allocationof the
costsof stabilization
whenit
occurs,the later
is the expecteddate
ofa
stabilization. Hence,if
unequal distributionof the
burden ofexperience longer periods of instability.2 More
institutional adaptation to the
distortions associated with instability also implieslater
expected stabilization, whilepartial attempts to
control
the
deficit prior to a full stabilization may make the expected time of full stabilization either earlier or later. We further showthat if
it
isthe
poor who suffer most fromthe
distortions associated with high government deficits and debt, they may bearthe
largest shareof the
costsof
stabilization. We also discussthe
relation ofthe
distribution of income tothe
timingof stabilization and
show conditions for a more unequaldistribution to
imply eitheran
earlieror
a
later
expecteddate of
stabilization.Our approach is related to the
literature
on dynamic games betweena
monetaryand
a
fiscalauthority
with conflicting objectives (Sargent [1986], Tabellini [1986,1987], Loewy [1988]).In that literature
a "warof attrition"
is played betweenthe two
branchesof
government:an
unsustainable combination
of
monetaryand
fiscal policies is in place until one side concedes.Our shift
in emphasisto
a game betweeninterest
groups has several justifications.First, the
assumption
that
the monetaryauthority
is independent ofthe
fiscalauthority
is unrealisticfor
most countries with serious problems
of
economicinstability.
Second,the
difference inthe
objective functions of different branches
of
government may be related totheir
representing different constituencies; here we tackle issuesof
heterogeneity directly.4 Finally, by explicitly modelling distributional conflicts, we can derive resultsrelating the
timing of stabilizationto
2The effects
of
political instability onthe path of
government debt is studied in a different framework by Alesinaand
Tabellini (1987,1989), Tabellini and Alesina (1989),and
Persson andSvensson (1989).
31n contrast, a model with heterogeneity, but with a social planner
or
benevolent government would predictthat
the burden of costs of stabilization would be more equitably distributed.4Rogoff (1985) has suggested
that it
may be optimalto
appointa
Central Banker with preferences wiuch do not coincide with social preferences. Inthis
case, however,the
Central Bank's preferences would be known bythe
public, whilea
warof attrition
requires uncertainty—4—
economic
and
political characteristicsof
different economies.The paper is organized
as
follows. Section 2 summarizes some regularities observed in anumber
of
stabilizations which suggest usinga
war ofattrition as a
model. Section 3 presentsa
specific stylized model
of the
process leading to a stabilization based onthe
empirical observations and shows how delaysresult
from individually rational behavior. Section 4presents comparative
static
results on howthe
expecteddate of
stabilization is affected by changes in the economy's characteristics. The final section presents conclusionsand
suggests extensions.II. Delayed Stabilization as a War
of Attrition
No single model can explain every episode
of
delay in enacting a macroeconomicstabilization. Historical evidence suggests, however,
that
in a large numberof
hyperinfiations,it
was disagreement over allocating the burden of fiscal change which delayedthe
adoption of a new policy. We begin by noting common featuresof
the stabilization process across severalepisodes, features which suggest modelling stabilization as a war
of attrition.
1. There is agreement over
the
need fora
fiscal change,but a
political stalemate overhow
the
burdenof
higher taxesor
expenditure cuts should be allocated.In the political
debate over stabilization,this
distributional question is central.Sharp disagreements over over allocating
the
burden of paying for the war were commonin
the
belligerent countries after World WarI
(Alesina [1988], Eichengreen [1989]). Forexample,
in
France, Germany, andItaly, the
politicalbattle
over monetary and fiscal policywas not over
the
need for reducinglarge
budget deficits, but over which groups should bear thehigher taxes
to
achievethat
end. Partiesof
theright
favored proportional income and indirect taxes; partiesof
the left favored capital levies and more progressive income taxes (Haig [1929).Maier [1975]). Though Britain after the war also faced a problems
of
fiscal stabilization,the
dominant position of
the
Conservatives ledto
a
rapid stabilization by means which favoredthe
Conservatives'traditional
constituencies. Oncethe
need forsharply restrictive
aggregate demand policies to endthe
Israeli inflation was widely accepted,5there
was still astalemate
over distribution: specifically,there
was an unwillingnessby
labor to accept sharp drops in employment and real wages.2. When stabilization occurs
it
coincideswith
a political consolidation. Often, one sidebecomes politically dominant. The burden
of
stabilization is sometimesquite
unequal,with the
politically weaker groups bearing a larger burden. Oftenthis
meansthe
lower classes, withsuccessful stabilizations being regressive.
The
successful stabilizationsin
France (1926) andItaly
(1922—24) coincided witha
clear consolidation of power bythe
right. In both cases, the burden fell disproportionately onthe
working class (Haig [1929], Maier [1975]).The
German stabilization of November 1923 followed a newEnabling
Act givingthe
new Stresemann government powerto cut
through legislative deadlocks and quicklyadopt
fiscal measures by decree. Thoughthe
government which took power in August wasa
"Grand
Coalition"of the
right andthe
left, byautumn "the
farright
was more dangerous and powerfulthan the socialist left" and government policy reflected
the
perceived need to appease conservativeinterest
groups (Maier [1975], pp. 384—6).The Israeli
stabilization
also occurred witha
National Unity government inpower
more importantly, what distinguished theJul
program from earlier failedattempts
wasthe
heavierIn
the
early 1980'sthere
was substantial disagreement over whether high inflation was due to—6—
burden
it
would place on labor. Onthe other
side,the
failure of Argentina to stabilizein the
face of endemic inflation has gone hand in hand with continued political polarization andinstability and the failure of
any
groupto
consolidateits
power effectively (Dornbusch and DePablo[1988]).3. Successful stabilizations are usually preceded by several failed
attempts;
often a orevious program appears Quite similarto the
successful one.In a
warof attrition the
cost of waiting meansthat the
passageof time
will imply concession onthe
same termsthat
a player earlier found "unacceptable".The
components ofthe successful Poincare stabilization of 1926 are quite similar to
his
program of 1924. Several unsuccessfulattempts
in Germany appear quite similarex ante to the
November 1923 program(Dornbusch [1988]). Many aspects
of
theJuly
1985 stabilizationin Israel
bad been previouslyproposed, but rejected by
the
government.To summarize, the central role of conflict over how the burden
of
stabilization isto
lieshared; the importance
of
political consolidation in the adoptionof
a program; andthe
factthat
programs which were previously rejectedate
agreedto after the
passage of time suggestsmodelling delayed stabilization as arising from a war
of attrition
between differentsocio—economic groups.
In the
basic warof attrition
model from biology, two animals are fighting over a prize. Fightingis
costly,and the
fight ends when one animal drops out,with the
other gainingthe
prize. Supposethat the
two contestants are not identical, either in the costsof
remainingn
the
fight or inthe
utility they assignto the
prize. Supposefurther that
each contestant's valueof
these is known only to himself, his opponent knowing only the distribution of these values.The
individual's problem is to choose a stopping time based on his type,that
is,the
value
of
his costs and payoffs, onthe
distributionof
his opponent's possible type,and on the
knowledgethat
his opponent is solvingthe
same choice problem.That is, he
choosesa
time to concedeif
his opponent has not already conceded. In equilibriumthe time of
concession is determined bythe
conditionthat at
the
optimal time,the
costof
remaining inthe
fight another instantof
time is Just equalto the
expected gain from remaining, namelythe
probability
that the
rival drops outat that instant
multiplied bythe
gainif the
rival concedes. Atthe
beginningof the
contestthe
gain to remaining exceedsthe
gain to dropping out, asthere
is some probability
that
one's opponent isof
atype that
drops out early.The
passageof time
with no concession on hispart
conveys the information thatthis
is notthe
case,until one's
ownconcession occurs according to the above criterion.
For a war
of attrition
between heterogeneous individualsto
give expected finite delayin
concession under incomplete information, two obvious features
are important.
First,there
must
be
a cost to remaining in the fight, that isto
not conceding. Second, the payoffto
thewinner must exceed
that
tothe
loser.In
the next section we show how stabilizations maybe
modelled with these features in mind.
II. The Model
We consider an economy as
in
Drazen and Helpman (1987,1989) in whichthe
government is running a positive deficit (inclusive
of
debt service) implying growinggovernment
debt.
Stabilization Consists ofan
increase in taxes which bringsthe
deficitto
zero, sothat
government debt is constant. We assumethat
priorto
an agreement on how to6Since we
are
considering an economy with constant output. this is equivalent to a rising—8—
share
the
burdenof
highertaxes, the
government islimited to
highly inefficientand
distortionary methods of public finance.7In
particular, monetizationof
deficits,with
the associated costsof
highand
variable inflation, is oftena
main sourceof
government revenue prior toa
fiscal stabilization. The level of distortionary financing, and hencethe
welfare lossassociated
with it,
rises withthe
level of government debt. These welfare losses may differacross socio—econornic groups:
for
examplethe
poor may havefar
less accessto
assets which protectthem
against inflation.€A second type of cost
to
continuing in a war ofattrition
is more directly political. Fora
group
to
prevent the burden of a stabilization being placed onit,
it must mobilizeand
use resources for lobbying activities to influencethe
outcomeof
the legislativeor
electoral jrocess. Different groups may differ in their political influenceand
thereforein the
level of effort needed to continue fightingthe
warof attrition.
We develop the model stressing the firstinterpretation of
pre—stabilization costs, but willreturn to
political interpretations inthe
concluding section.The benefit
of
stabilization derives from the move away from highly distortionary methodsof
financing government expenditures.In this
respect, stabilization benefitseverybody. The differential benefits reflect
the
factthat
the increasein
nondistortionary taxes is unequally distributed.Concession in our model is
the
agreement by one side to bear a disproportionate shareof
TCukierman, Edwards , and Tabellini (1989),
for
example, arguethat
unstable LDC's often exhibit highly inefficient fiscal systems in which it is extremely difficultto
raisestandard
income taxes, leading to reliance on inflation and very wasteful formsof taxation.
Tbe
view thatthe utility
loss from living in an unstabilized economy flows fromthe
useof
distortionary financing ofpart
ofthe
government deficit raisesan
obvious question: why not simply accumulate debtuntil an
agreemwnt can be reached on levying less distortionary taxes? We suggestthere
maybe
constraints onthe rate
of growth ofthe
debt, especiallyif
it is external, but do not model this here.the tax
increase necessaryto
effect a stabilization. Interpreted literally,the
notion ofconcession which ends
the
war ofattrition
is not observed. However, asthe
examples inthe
previnus section illustrate, effective concession maybe
reflected in a formal agreement betweenthe
various sides, as in the Israeli case;in the the
formationof
a
new government which is given extraordinary powers, as inthe
Frenchor
German cases;or
inthe
outcomeof
elections in which one side gainsa
clear majority,and
opposing groups decide not to blocktheir
program any longer.9More formally, consider a small open economy which issues external
debt to
cover any deficits not covered byprinting
money. The economy is composedof
a number ofheterogeneous interest groups which differ from one another in
the
welfare loss they suffer fromthe
distortions associatedwith the
pre—stabilization methodsof
government finance. We will first specify government behavior, then the maximizing behaviorof interest
groups. This characterizesthe
warof attrition
leadingto
a stabilization. Fromthis
process we can derivean
endogenous distribution of
time of
stabilization.Until
t =
0 the government budget is balanced, with external government debt constantat
levelb0 0. At
t =
0 a shockhits
reducing availabletax
revenues. Fromt =
0 untilthe date
of stabilizationa
fraction ofthe
deficit 1 —y is covered by issuing debt and a
fraction by distortionary taxation. (Though the economy is non—monetary, a major type of
distortionary taxation is inflation arising from printing money.) What is
important for
usis
notthat
'
is fixed, butthat
it
is positive. Calling g0 the level of expenditures aftert =
0,debt
b(t)
evolves accordingto
9Elections may give one side
a
clear mandate not becauseits
opponents have conceded on their distributional objectives, but because a majority of voters seethat
side as more competentto
— 10 —
(1)
b(t)
=
(1—')(rb(t)+
g0)where r is
the
worldinterest rate,
assumed to be constant. This maybe
solved to yield(2)
b(t)
=
b0e(1_7)rt+
e(1_7)Tt
—1).
Defining
b0
+
,
taxes before a stabilizationare
(3)
T(t)= (rb(t)
+
g0)=
eTt.
A stabilization consists
of an
increase in taxes sufficientto
preventfurther
growth inthe
debt.
Hence taxesto be
leviedat the date of
stabilizationT are
r(T) =
rb(T)+
where is the level
of
expenditures after a stabilization. If we assume for simplicitythat
=
g0, we have from(2)
(4)
r(T)
=
re(1_T.
An agreement
to
stabilize isan
agreement on how the taxes T(T)are
tobe
apportioned between different interest groups. For simplicity assumethere are
only two groups (an assumption easily generalized). The "stabilizer" assumesa
fractiona
> 1/2of the tax
burdenat T, the "non—stabilizer"
a
fraction 1 — a. The fractiona
itself
is not bargained on: it isa
givenparameter meant
to capturethe
degree of polarization inthe
society. A valueof
a
closeto one represents
a
high degreeof
polarizationor
a
lackof
political cohesiveness.Taxes after
a
stabilization are assumed to be non—distortionary. What isimportant
isthat
they are1
d.istortionarythan
taxes beforea
stabilization. In fact,if
taxes after astabilization
were equally distortionary, there would in generalbe
no incentiveto
concede,that
is, to stabilize.Infinitely—lived groups may differ from one another in two respects. One is
their
flow endowment of incomey.
The second isthe utility
loss they suffer dueto
distortionary taxes.Let us
index
groupi's
loss by0,
where 0 is drawn froma
distributionF(),
with lower and upper bounds 9 and.
What is critical isthat
0
is known only tothe
group itself, other groups knowing onlythe
distribution F(0).The
results on delayed stabilizationare
consistentwith
a
functionalrelation
betweeny
and0,
as long as0
cannotbe
inferred.(For
example withuncertainty about the
marginal utility of income.) For simplicity we assume that theutility loss from distortionary taxes,
K,
is linear in the levelof taxes,
namely'°K(t)
=
Ojr(t)The flow
utility
of group i is linear in consumptionand
isof the
formu(t)
=
— —'°\Ve could adopt a more general specification for
K,
such asK(t)
= O(,())l+m
withm>
0.The
qualitative
featuresof
our results do not change withthis
more general specification. The differences will be emphasized below.— 12 —
where c is consumption. (Subtracting
y
is simplya
normalization.) After a stabilization= 0, as
taxes aftera
stabilization are assumed tobe
non—distortionary. We suppress the Isubscript
onthe
functionu.
If is independentof
y,
distributionof
income does not affectthe
timingof
stabilization. We considerthe
alternative casein
section IV.The
objective of each group isto madmize
expected present discountedutility
by choiceof
atime
path of consumption anda date to
concede and agree to bearthe share
a
of
taxesif
the other
group has not already conceded. Let us denote flowutility
before a stabilization byuD(t) and
the lifetimeutility of the
stabilizer andthe
non—stabilizer fromthe date
ofstabilization onward by
vS(T) and
VN(T) respectively. Lifetimeutility of the
stabilizer andthe
non—stabilizerif
stabilization occursat
timeT
may then be written asT
U1(T)
=
J
u(x)ed.x
+
e_rTVJ(T)j
=
S,N.0
Expected
utility as of
time zeroas a
functionof
one's chosen concessiontime
T1 is the sum ofUN(T) multiplied by the probability of one's opponent conceding
at T for
allT
< T1and
US(Ti) multiplied bythe
probabilityof
one's opponent not having conceded byT.
If we denote by 11(T)the
distribution ofan
opponent's optimaltime of
concession(this
is of courseendogenous and will
be
derived below)and
byh(T) the
associated density function, expectedutility as
a functionof
T
is1T. N
=
(1 —H(T))
[JTiuD(X)e_rxdx+
e_rTi
vS(T)J
+
J:=
uD(z)e_dz
+
e_TXVN(x)]h(x)dxThe time path of
consumption and T1 are chosen to maximize (8).With
linearutility any
consumption path satisfyingthe intertemporal
budget constraint with equality gives equalutility.
Denote byD,
cS, andcN
consumption beforea
stabilization, after
a
stabilization forthe
"stabilizer", and after a stabilization forthe
'non—stabilizer" respectively. Assumingthat
eachof the
two groups pays one—halfof
taxes before a stabilization, we havethe
lifetime budget constraintsrT
(9)
j
cU(x)e)Cdx+
Jc(x)e
dx=
J(y
—(x))edx
+
JT(
—e(1_T)e_tx
(10) JTcD(x)e_rxdx+
JzcN(x)e_lx
=
—x))edx
+
J(
—(l_)r1_7T)edx.
The following consumption
path
is then clearly feasible(ha)
cD(t)=
y
—re(1_t
0
<t <
T
— 14 —
(lic)
cN(t)=
—(l_a)re(1_'T
t
T
11 Flowutility
beforea
stabilization isthen
(12)
u?(t)
=
—re(1_7)rt
—=
—'r(
+
Oi)&e(1_7t
which is
the
income effect of taxes plusthe
welfare loss arising from taxes being distortionary. (Notethat
we assumethat the
distortionary costto
each group depends onthe total
levelof
distortionarytaxes.)
With
constant consumption after a stabilization, discountedutility
(j
=
N,S) is simply constant flowutility for
eachgroup
divided by r. Using (11) and (6)(with
K
=
0) one immediately obtains(13)
v'(T)
— VS(T)=
(2n —which is
the
present discounted valueof the
excess taxesthat
the stabilizer mustpay
relativeto the
non—stabilizer.We are now ready to determine
T,
the
optimal concessiontime
for a group with cost 0.22 Since we do not knowthe
distribution H(T), we cannot use (8) directly. However, byshowing
that
is monotunic in O, we can derive therelation
betweenH(T)
andthe
known"Formally, a solution does not require consumption
to be
non—negativeat
each point; it is onlyrequired
that at
each pointat
whichan
individual does not concede,the utility
from remaining is higher than theutility
from dropping out.With
astandard
concaveutility
function the solution would havethe property of
no concession requiring non—negative consumption.F(0), namely (1—H[T(0)])
=
F(0). We therefore first establishLEMMA 1:
The
optimal concession timefor
group i is monotonicaliy decreasingin
O,
that
isT(81)
<
a'.Proof: See Appendix.
We now want to find a symmetric equilibrium where each group's concession behavior is described by a monotonically increasing function T(0). The
idea
here isto
showthat
there
exists a Nash equilibrium where
if
allother
groups are behaving according to T(O) groupi
finds
it
optimalto
concede according to T(0), and to characterize T(0).'3 Having donethat,
the
expected time of stabilization isthe
expected minimum T, withthe
expectationtaken
over F(0).PROPOSITION 1: There exists a symmetric Nash equilibrium with each group's optimal
behavior described by
a
concession function T(0), where T(0) is implicitly defined byT'(0)=—44
ru)
(2
—1)/r
+
-
and
the
boundary condition'3There may also
be
assymetric equilibria(that
is, where groups behave accordingto
differentT(O)) even though each group's 0
is
knownto
be drawn fromthe
same distribution F(0). Wedo not investigate
them
and restrict ourattention
tothe
symmetric equilibrium.Of
course,if
different groups' endowments
are
perceived tobe
drawn from different distributions, each groupwill have a different
— 16 —
(15)
T()=O.
Proof: See Appendix
To
understandthe nature
ofthe
optimal strategy, we may write (14) as(16)
[f3i]2a_
(o+.a)
The right
hand
side isthe
costof
waiting another instant to concede.The
left—hand side isthe
expected gain to waiting another instantto
concede, which isthe
productof
the conditionalprobability
that
one's opponent concedes(the
hazard rate, in brackets) multiplied bythe
gainif
the other group concedes. Concession occurs whenthe
(group—specific) costof
waiting justequals
the
expected benfit from waiting. This isa standard result
inthe
warof attrition.
Equation (16) is also useful in understandingthe
evolutionof
the war ofattrition
fromthe viewpoint of one side. Consider a group
with
9>
.
At time
zerothere
is some probabilitythat it's
opponent has 9=
and will concede immediately. Formally, with fiV)> 0,
the
left—hand side of (16) is infinite, so the group does not concede.If
no one concedes attime
zero, both sides know their opponent is not type.
At the
"next"instant the
next—highest type concedes,
and
so on, so astime
passes each side learnsthat
its opponent is not of cost above acertain
level. When the conditional probabilityof an
opponent's concession inthe
nextinstant
(based on whatthe
group has learned about his highest possible cost) issuch
that
(16)just
holds,its
time to "throw inthe
towel."expected minimum T.
the
expectation taken over F(9).With n
players the probabilitythat
a given9
is the maximum (sothat T(9)
isthe
minimum) isits
density f(O) multipliedby
the probability
that
no other 9 is higher, namely(F(O))°1,
multiplied by n.With n
2,the
expected valueof
minimum T,that is, the
expectedtime of
stabilization TSE, isthus
TSE
=
2J 9 T(x)F(x)f(x)dx.
As long as all
participants
inthe
process initially believethat
someone else has may have a higher 9, stabilization does not occur immediately. The cumulative distribution ofstabilization times
T
is therefore one minus the probabilitythat
every group hasa
0 lowerthan the
value consistent with stabilizationat
T. With two groups this isS(T)
=
1(F(TI))2
where 9(T) is defined by T(O) T.
Two observations are useful in helping
to
explain the key roleof
heterogeneity.Consider first what
the
model would implyif
all groups were identical,that is, if
we considered a representative agent model.If
weinterpret
this as there being a single agent, he knows with probability onethat
he willbe the
stabilizer. Since uD is negative, equation (8) impliesthat
expected
utility
is maximized by choosingT
equalto
zero,that
is, by stabilizing immediately. Intuitively,if an
individual knowsthat he
will endup
bearingthe
cost ofa
stabilization, a cost to waiting implies
that
it is optimal toact
immediately.Heterogeneity alone is not sufficient, however, to explain why stabilization is postponed. There must also be uncertainty
about the
costto
waiting of other groups. Ifit
is known toai
— 18 —
that
a
group has higher coststhan
anyone else, optimal behavior willimply
that
this
group concedes immediately. Intuitively, stabilization is postponed because eachinterest
groupbelieves in
the
possibilitythat
another group will give up first. As time passes and this expectation is not realized, one group finally concedes.It
is also interesting to comparethe
sensein
which stabilization becomes "inevitable" .here tothe
sense used in Sargent and Wallace (1981) and Drazen and Helpman (1987.1989). Inthose papers a positive deficit (exclusive
of
debt service) impliesthat
government debt isgrowing faster than the rate of interest, so
that its
present value is not goingto
zero.The
failureof
this transversality condition to hold, and hencethe
long—run infeasibility ofthe path,
is what makes stabilization inevitable.
In
our modelthe
warof attrition
ends infinite time
with a stabilization, evenif
the path ofthe
debt is technically feasible,that
is, evenif it
growsless fast
than the rate of
interest. Hence our approach indicates why countries whose policies are technically feasible (present discounted valueof the
debt goesto
zero) will eventuallystabilize
if
current policies involve welfare loss.'
IV.
Comparative StaticsWe can now ask how various changes in
the
parametersor
distributions affectthe
expectedtime
ofa
stabilization. Our goal is to seeif
observable characteristics of economies explain why some countries stabilize soonerthan
others. We present these results ina
numberof
propositions, and explain each result intuitively. Proofs are in the appendix.PROPOSITION 2: Higher Distortionarv Taxes
or
MonetizationWhen the
utility
loss from distortionary taxation is proportional to the levelof
taxes, financinga greater fraction of
the
pre—stabilization deficit via distortionarytaxation
(a higher-) implies
an
earlierdate
of stabilization.This result may seem initially surprising, for
it
saysthat an attempt to
controlthe
growthof
government indebtedness may actually hastenthe date of
stabilization. A higher yon
the
one hand implies a greater distortionfor
a
given deficit, inducing playersto
concede earlier. However, making moreof an
effortto
reducethe
deficit impliesthat
government debt grows lessfast
and hencethe
distortions which induce stabilization also grow less fast. The reason the first effect dominates isthat
our proportional specification in (5) impliesthat both
the
gain from beingthe
non—stabilizer andthe
loss from no stabilizationare
proportional to thesize of
the
debt, sothat
a slower growth ofthe
debt does not initself
change their relativemagnitudes. '5 Higher monetization, for example, has the effect of raising
the
cost of living in theunstabilized economy relative
to
the gain from having another group stabilizeat
each point inunLe. This result is consistent with
the
idea that is is easierto
stabilize hyperinflations than irsflations whichare
"only" high.PROPOSITION 3: Higher Costs
of
DistortionsAn increase
in the
costs associated with livingin an
unstabilized economy,for an
unchanged distributionof
9, will movethe
expecteddate of
a stabilization forward.lsWhen the
utility
loss from distortionary taxation rises more than proportionally with the level of taxes(as
in footnote 10). the effect of slower growthof the
deficit may dominate.It
can be shown (details are available)that
low 0 groups will concede later, sothat
ifit
happensthat
both groups have low 0, increasedy
will mean alater
dateof
stabilization.— 20 —
Countries with
institutions that
lessenthe utility
loss from distortionary financingof
government expenditures (suchas
indexation) will, other things equal, be expected to postponestabilization longer. The caveat here is
that
increased indexation may induce greater monetizationor
higher prices for a given levelof
monetization. This appears relevant forthe
Israeli case.If
the utility
loss is an increasing (perhaps convex) function of inflation, a sharp accelerationof
inflation will lead to a stabilization.This
would explainthe timing of the
French and German stabilizations.
PROPOSITION 4: Lower Political Cohesion
If a =
1/2 stabilization occurs immediately; the larger isa
above 1/2,the later
isthe
expecteddate of
stabilization.The difference in the shares of
the
burdenof
stabilization,a,
could beinterpreted
asrepresenting the degree
of
political cohesion inthe
society. Countrieswith
a
close to 1/2 canbe
characterized as having high political cohesionin that
the
burdenof
stabilization is sharedrelatively equally, while those where
the
burden is very unequal, sothat
a
is closeto
one,are
more polarizedor
less cohesive. Whenthe
relative burdenof
a stabilization is very unequallydistributed, the
gainto
waiting inthe
hope that one's opponent will concede is larger. Henceeach group holds out longer.
This
intuitive result
suggestsa
relationship between certain measuresof
political stability and macroeconomic outcomes. Roubini and Sachs (l989a,b) arguethat
governments composed of large, short—lived, and uncohesive coalitions are associated withlarge
budget deficits. They construct an indexof
political cohesion and stability in the government andshow a strong correlation between
that
indexand
budget deficits after 1973 in severalindustrial
countries. One explanationof
this finding consistent with our model concerns reachingdecisions within
the
coalition. Large coalitions of politically diverse parties findit
particularly
hard
to reach agreement on how allocatetax
increases or expenditure cuts amongthe
constituencies represented by coalition partners. In
the
absenceof
such agreement, deficits grow.It
should be emphasized, however,that
empirical correlations between political and economicinstability
do not establish causation in one direction. Though we emphasize a causal link from politicalto
economicinstability,
there may of coursebe
causal kinksin the
opposite direction. 26Greater dispersion in
the
distributionof
income or resources can affectthe
timing ofstabilization if
a group's cost 9 is a functionof its
income. Since delayed stabilization requires relative cost be unknown toother
groups,this
means that relative positions in the income distribution must be unknown. We find suchan
assumption somewhat problematic. An increase in income inequality mayitself
make relative positionsapparent,
leadingto an
immediate stabilization.if
one is willing to acceptuncertainty
about relative income, naiveintution
suggeststhat
a mean—preserving spread in the distributionof
income will lead to anea:..er date
ofstabilization, since it means some group will have a higher cost and
thus conceá
earlier. Such reasoning is incomplete, for it ignores the change in behavior(that
is, in the func.n
1(0))
induced by the change
in the
distribution of costs. Thefatter
upper tail for costs, meansthat
each group perceivesa
higher likelihood thatits
opponents' costs have increased.his
'6For
a
recent insightful study of economic determinants of politicalinstability,
See Londegran— 22 —
perception wou.ld lead it
to
hold out longer. When willthis latter
effect dominate, sothat
a greater dispersion in income could leadto
later expected stabilization?PROPOSITION 5: Income Dispersion
and
Longer Delaysin
StabilizingIf the
utility
loss due to distortionary taxes isa
decreasing, convex function of income, andincome is unobservable, a mean—preserving spread in
the
distributionof
income G(y)that
keepsthe
expected minimum ofthe
y's constant implies alater
expecteddate
of stabilization.Note
that if 9' (y)
<
0, it isthe
"poor" who stabilize, since the "rich" suffer from the distortions arising from budget deficits less and thus can hold out longer. The crucial assumption of uncertainty about income is perhaps more reasonable underthe
secondinterpretation of
costs in section II, namely as resourcesthat
mustbe
devoted to the political process to avoid bearing a disproportionate share of the burden of stabilization.y
would thenbe resources available forpolitical purposes.
With
uncertaintyboth
about the relative politicalskills of groups and about what fraction
of
their resources they are willing to devoteto the
political struggle, assuming uncertainty about relative "income" seems more defensible. An empirical finding consistent
with
Proposition 5 is presented by Berg and Sachs(1988), who find
a
strong empirical relation betweenthe
degreeof
income inequality and the frequency of debt rescheduling. Countries with a more unequal income distribution haveexperienced more difficulties in servicing their external debt. Although
this
evidence is not directlyrelated to the
timingof
stabilization policies,it
is consistent withthe idea that
countries with more income inequality will,at
a given level of debt, findit
more difficultto
adopt
policies necessary toinsure
solvency and service the debt.IV.
Extensions -We have presented a model showing how delayed stabilization can
be
explained in a modelof
rational heterogeneous agents.In
contrast,the
same model with arational
representative individual would yield immediate stabilization. Since we summarized many
of
the
results inthe
introductory section, we c9nclude first by discussing some generalizations and second by touching on some issues whichthe
model did not address but which are important inexplaining stabilization.
First, we used
the
exampleof
tax
increases made necessary by budget deficits inducing a war ofattrition
because it is particularly relevant for hyperinflations.Our
argument is far more general. Any policy change with strong distributional consequences can give riseto
a
warof
attrition.
Second, for simplicity we considered
a
case wherethere
was no changein
external circumstances followingthe
original shock. More generally, oncea
war ofattrition
has been going on, a change in the environment (including aid or intervention from abroad) may lead toa change in agents' behavior and rapid concession by one side. Even (or especially) when
this
change is forseen,
the
warof attrition
is crucial in the delayof
stabilizationuntil the
external change.A
third
generalization is a more precise formalization ofthe
political process leadingto
stabilization.
In particular,
this would leadto
a
more satisfactory characterizationof
the political costs involved in sheltering oneself from bearing the burden of stabilization. As in the model above, such costs may increase with the sizeof the outstanding debt:
asthe
difference between payoffs to winnersand
losers rise, as aresult of
the growing levelof the debt,
each side should be willing to expend more time and resources in activities such as lobbyingto
inducesits
—24—
such direct political
costs
willbe
centralto
the timingof
concession. We did not model this formally, since the simplicity of our model depended on costs being simply proportional to current taxes,an
assumption which appears difficultto
justifyfor
political costs. Nonetheless we think political costsare
no lessimportant
than costsof
distortionsin the
warof
attrition.A
political model also suggestsalternative
interpretationsof
someof
our results. For example, in Proposition 3, the effectof
a shiftin
U could beinterpreted as
follows. Countrieswith
politicalinstitutions
which makeit
relatively more difficult for opposing groups to "veto"stabilization
programs notot their
liking will stabilize sooner.Finally,
let
us note some issues we did not discuss. First, delays in successfulstabilization are related
to the
issueof
failed stabilization and hence to what determines the probabilityof
success. Sargent (1982,1984) identified "credibility" as a crucial ingredientof
success, where a "credible" stabilization is program is one in which a "strong" policymaker isfirmly committed
to the
plan and is not likely to give into
pressure to abandon fiscalresponsibility
and revert to
inflationary finance. If the public is uncertainabout the
degree ofcommitment of
the
policymakerto
fiscal responsibility, success is seento be
less likely.17Dornbusch (1988) criticizes
this
notionof
credibility becauseof
a
lack of predictive power, arguingthat
successfuland
unsuccessful programs often appearquite
similar ex ante. As examples, be refersto
Poincare's successful 1926 stabilization in comparison with hisunsuccessful 1924
attempt,
andto the
several unsuccessfulattempts
in Germany priorto the
November 1923 program.In our model Sargent's notion of credibility plays no role. Instead our model suggests
that
stabilizations need not be associated either with a sharp change in external circomstances.'TBackus and Driffill (1985), Barro (1986), and Tabellini (1988?
study
dynamic games in whichnor with the program being implemented looking sharply different
than
what had previously been proposed. A program which was unsuccessfulat
one point intime
maylater be
successful(thus
"credible" in Sargent's words) simply dueto the
passage of time.In
the warof attrition,
passage
of time and the
accumulation of costs leads one groupto
give inand
makea
previously rejected program economically and politically feasible.Second, in reality successful stabilizations are not one—shot affairs. One component of
success is designing how
the
adjustment process shouldbe
spread out over time.Our
notionof
timing was in
the
timing ofthe
beginning of a successful program,not of the
timingof its
stages onceit
has begun. On a basic level, these could be separated,with this
paper addressingthe
questionof
why significant policy changes, multistage or otherwise,are
delayed. In fact, since stabilization takes time, programs often appear successful for a period of time, only to subsequently fail. Hence,the
issueof
delayed stabilization should ideallybe
considered simultaneously with issuesof
both partial and multistage stabilizations.Finally, we
have
not explicitly consideredimportant
political events suchas
elections.The
timing of elections may berelated to the
timingof
stabilizations. An electoralresult
favorable to one side may make
it
far
more difficult for their opponents to block their programsand
shelter themselves fromthe
costsof
stabilization. Thus, one might expect successfulstabilizations following elections with a clear winner. In
the
terminologyof
our model, a clear electoral result maybe an important
signalof
the distribution ofthe
relative strengthof
A—i
APPENDIX
Proof of Lemma
1Differentiating (8) with respect to
T1 one obtains(Al)
=
eTi
[h(TxvN(Ti)
—vS(Ti))
+
s
dVS(T.)
(1
—H(T1))(u(T1)
—rV (Ti)
+
dT
)] Usingthe
definitionsof
vN(T), vS(T), and
u(t)
(Al)
becomes(A2)
=eTi
{h(T1)(2a_i)e(_'rTi
+
(1
—H(T))
[yr(
— — O&e(1_7)1Ti]] Differentiatingwith
respectto
8
weobtain
(A3) — (1 —
H(T1))e(_7)tTi
<
Equation (A3) means
that
whenothers
areacting optimally,
dEtJ/dT
is decreasing in O.Optimal
concessiontime
T
is therefore
monotonically decreasing in8.
Proof of Proposition
1(This
proof closely follows Blissand
Nalebuff [1984])Suppose
the other interest group
isacting
accordingto T(8),
the
optimal
concessiontime
fora
groupwith utility
cost 8. Choosinga
time
T
as above
would be equivalent to choosinga
valueand
concedingat
time
T
=
T(
9k). Equation (8) becomes,after the
change in variables
(A4)
EU(O,8)
=
F(Oi))uD(x)e_rT(x)T(x)dx
+
e_rT(Oi)VS(T())]
+
[JuD(z)e_rTT(z)dz
+
e_rT(VN(T(x))]f(x)dx.
Differentiating with respect
to 9
and setting the resulting expression equalto
zero we obtain (where we dropthe
i subscript)(A5); dEU
=
f(O)[(/S(T(9))
—
vN(Tj))]
+
F(9)(u (0,9) — ryS
+
.T_)T'(G)
=
0. winch becomes after substitutions(A6)
ii1
=
— f(9)(2a—1)—
F(0h'r(9
+
— a)T'(O)=
0.ao
Now by the definition of T(0) as
the
optimal timeof
concessionfor
a group with cost 9, 9=
0 when 9 is chosen optimally. The first—order condition (A6) evaluatedat
0=
9 implies(14).
(Substituting
T'(0)
evaluatedat
0 from (14) into (A6) one seesthat the
second order condition is satisfied, since (A6) then impliesthat
signdEU/d9
=
sign (9— 9).) To derivethe
initial
boundary condition note firstthat
for any valueof
0,
the gain to havingthe
opponent concede is positive. Therefore as long as
f()
is nonzero, groupswith
9<
will not concede immediately. This in turn impliesthat
a group with 0=
(that
is,that
knows it hasthe
highest possible costof
waiting) will findit
optimal to concede immediately. ThusT()
=
Proof
of
Proposition 2A higher fraction
of
pre—stabilization deficits financed bytaxation
correspondsto
a
higher valueof
y. Comparingthe
optimal timeof
concession as a function of 0for
y>
y,we
haveT'(0)=_.43
(2a —l)/r
(0
+
-
(A7)T'(9) =
(2cr—1)/r
y(9+-a)
Since — is
the
same in bothA—3
-y,
that
is,
T(V)=
T()
= 0.
Inspection of (A7) indicatesthat T'(8)
>
T'(8)
for all values of8. Combining these two
results,
we havethat
T(O) > T(8) for U<
.
Equation (17)then
implies
that
TSE>
j.SEProof
of
Proposition 3A multiplicative shift in 8
has an
identical effect to an increase in 'y in Proposition 2. Byan
argument analogous
to the
one used inthat
proof, T(O) will shift down and henceTSE
willfall.
Proof
of Proposition 4When
a
=
1/2,vS =
vN.
Sincethere
are coststo
not conceding,it
is optimalto
concede immediately. To provethe
secondpart of the
proposition,the
same argument as in Proposition 2 showsthat
T()
=
T()
= 0
fora>
a. Sincethe
right—hand sideof
(14) increaseswith
an increase ina,
T'(8) >
T'(O) for all values of 0. Usingthe
same reasoningas in
Proposition 2, we havethat
T(O)> T(O)
for8 <
.
Equation (17) then impliesthat
TSE >
jSE
Proof
of
Proposition 5Suppose
8
=
with 8'
< 0, where a group's incomey
is unobservable. LetG(y,o)
bethe
distribution of income with bounds and,
where increasesin
correspondto a
more disperse income distribution. Increasing o' correspondsto a
mean—preserving spreadof
incomeif
for somey
G(y,)
0 for y yG(y,o)0
fory>yThe expected minimum value of y can be written as
which by
integration
byparts
equals I (1 — G(x,o))2dx.Constant expected y
implies
(A9)
j
(1
— G(x,o))G(x,o)dx
=
0.a
(A9) and (17) in
the
textimply
SE
ry(AlO)
T
(a) =
2jT(x,a)(1
— G(x,a))g(x,a)dx.Repeated integration
byparts
impliesthat
(AlO) canbe written as
TSE
2c_11)'
1dx
(a) =
j
(1 — G(x,a))g(x,a)2a—
ir
—1/2
+JRl—G(
x,a))
2 1=
r7
LO(
+
— a 0(x)+
—a' 0'(x)dx].
If
the
change ina
does not affectthe
lower boundand if
0, we havedTSE(a)
— — 2a — 1J(i
— G(x,a))G(x,a
_____
____
1 1)2
0'(x)dx]
da
—r
a0(x)
+
—a
2a— 10'(y)
2J(l_G(x,a))Ga(x,a)
=0.
- T7 a)REFERENCES
Alesina, A.,
"The
End of Large Public Debts," in F. Giavazziand
L. Spaventa, eds. Survivingwith a
High Public Debt Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1988.and
G. Tabethni,"External
Debt, Capital Flight,and
Political Risk," working paper, 1989 (forthcoming Journalof
International Economics).and ,
"A
Positive Theoryof
Fiscal Deficits and Government Debt," NBERWorking
Paper.
Backus, D. and J. Driffihl, "Inflation and Reputation," American Economic Review 75 (1985),
530—38.
Barro R., "Reputation in a Model of Monetary Policy with Incomplete Information,"
Journal of
Monetary Economics 17 (1986), 1—20.Berg, A. and
J.
Sachs, "The Debt Crisis: Structural Explanationsof
Country Performance," NBER Working Paper 2607, 1988.Bliss, C. and B. Nalebuff, "Dragon—Slaying and Ballroom Dancing:
The Private
Supplyof
aPublic Good,"
Journal of
Public Economics 25 (1984), 1—12.Cukierrnan, A., S. Edwards,
and
G. Tabellini, "Political Instability and Inflation in LDC's," working paper, 1989.Dornbusch
R.,
"Notes on Credibility and Stabilization," NBER WorkingPaper
2790, 1988.and J.C.
DePablo, "Argentine Debt and MacroeconomicInstability,"
NBER Working Paper 2378, 1987.and S. Fischer, "Stopping Hyperinflations
Past
and Present,"Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv 122 (1986), 1—46.Drazen, A. and E. Helpman, "Stabilization with Exchange Rate Management," Quarterly
Journal of Economics 52 (1987), 835—55.
and , "Inflationary Consequences of Anticipated Macroeconomic Policies," working paper, 1989 (forthcoming Review of Economic Studies).
Eichengreen,
B.,
"The Capital Levyin
Theory and Practice," working paper, 1989.Fudenberg, D. and J. Tirole, "A Theory
of Exit
in Duopoly," Econometrica 1986Haig, R., The Public Finance of Postwar France, Columbia University Press: New York, 1929.
Helpman, E. and L. Leiderman, "Stabilization in High Inflation Countries: Analytical Foundations and Recent Experience," Carnegie—Rochester Conference Series on Public